Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
69
Re-Affirming the Value of the Sports Exception
to Title IX’s General Non-Discrimination Rule
D
ORIANE LAMBELET COLEMAN* MICHAEL J. JOYNER** DONNA LOPIANO***
It all grew from the power of an idea.
1
I
NTRODUCTION
In just two years, we will celebrate Title IX’s fiftieth anniversary. The statute
was designed to address pervasive sex inequality in educational settings,
including in admissions and programming, and in benefits and treatment.
Although sex equality in education-based sport was not an original focus of Title
IX’s proponents, it became an integral part of the project from the date of its
enactment in 1972. Indeed, by the time the statute was in effect re-enacted in 1988,
Title IX had become synonymous with sport.
2
Title IX’s structure reflects a hybrid approach to sex equality. That is, the
statute consists of a sex-blind non-discrimination rule, and its regulations contain
a set of limited, sex-affirmative exceptions. Thus, the statutory text provides in
relevant part that
[n]o person in the United States shall, on the basis of sex, be excluded from
participation in, be denied the benefits of, or be subjected to discrimination under
any education program or activity receiving Federal financial assistance.
3
And the exceptions permit schools to take sex into account to address
imbalances in admissions, academic programming, and sport.
4
Because these
Copyright © 2020 by Doriane Lambelet Coleman, Michael J. Joyner, and Donna Lopiano.
* Professor of Law, Duke Law School.
** Caywood Professor of Anesthesiology and Perioperative Medicine, Mayo Clinic School of Medicine.
*** Adjunct Professor of Sports Management, Southern Connecticut State University. President,
Sports Management Resources. Former Chief Executive Officer of the Women’s Sports Foundation and
Director of Women’s Athletics at the University of Texas at Austin.
1. Cary McTighe Musil, The Triumph of Title IX, M
S. MAG., Fall 2007, at 42, https://www.
feminist.org/education/TriumphsOfTitleIX.pdf (quoting Professor David Sadker, whose
groundbreaking work with his wife Professor Myra Sadker on gender bias and educational equity
helped to support the development and eventual success of Title IX).
2. See generally E
QUAL PLAY: TITLE IX AND SOCIAL CHANGE (Nancy Hogshead-Makar & Andrew
Zimbalist eds., 2007). See also infra notes 38–78 and accompanying text (setting out the history of Title
IX).
3. 20 U.S.C. § 1681 (2018).
4. 34 C.F.R. § 106 (2019); 34 C.F.R. §§ 106.41(a)–(b) (2019) (containing the general non-
discrimination provision and the sports exception to that provision).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
70 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
original regulations were specifically required by Congress,
5
they have
traditionally been accorded heightened deference by the courts and are tightly
woven into Title IX’s legal fabric.
6
This regulatory approach was designed to and has yielded extraordinary
results for women and girls, and for society more generally. The pre- and post-
Title IX narrative is well worn at this point: “Title IX has successfully changed the
lives of girls and of women educators, protecting their rights, broadening their
horizons and setting them up for success in later stages of their education and
careers.”
7
Still, coming almost two centuries after Mary Wollstonecraft’s original
argument for educating women, its recency still surprises.
8
There is this, for example, from The Harvard Crimson on November 15, 1968,
three years before Title IX became law:
Yale President Kingman Brewster announced yesterday that Yale will become
coeducational in September 1969. The announcement came shortly after the Yale
faculty approved with only one dissenting vote a plan to admit 250 freshman
women plus 250 upperclass women by transfer. Eventually 1500 women will be
admitted in addition to the 4000 male students .
. . The faculty first approved
under-graduate coeducation at Yale in 1962, after women graduate students had
been admitted for several years. The administration considered establishing an
independent coordinate college for women, similar to Radcliffe, two years ago.
Later, Vassar was invited to consider affiliating with Yale, but its trustees declined
to abandon Poughkeepsie for New Haven.
9
This last bit of regional disrespect was righted in The New York Times which,
a month later, reported that “[a] Radcliffe dormitory at Harvard is applying as a
unit for admission to Yale next year . . . to end the frustrations of semi-
5. Pursuant to a now-defunct process, the regulations were presented by Secretary Weinberger
to President Ford for his signature in May 1975, and then to Congress on June 4, 1975. From that date,
Congress had 45 days to review and approve or disapprove them. Letter from Caspar Weinberger,
Sec’y of the Dep’t of Health, Education, & Welfare, to the President (Feb. 28, 1975), at A-1–2 [hereinafter
Letter from Casper Weinberger] (delivering and explaining HEW’s final regulation), (on file with the
Gerald R. Ford Presidential Library). Had Congress failed to act, the regulations would have become
valid by default. Id. In its review period, senators and congressmen opposed to Title IX in its entirety
or as applied to sport presented a series of resolutions rejecting the regulations, but ultimately, on July
21, the regulations were approved. See History of Title IX, W
OMENS SPORTS FOUND. (Aug. 13, 2019),
https://www.womenssportsfoundation.org/advocate/title-ix-issues/history-title-ix/history-title-ix/.
We detail this history, including the still-active practice of according the regulations heightened
deference, infra at notes 40–69 and accompanying text.,
6. See, e.g., McCormick ex rel. McCormick v. Sch. Dist. of Mamaroneck, 370 F.3d 275, 286 (2d Cir.
2004) (summarizing the legislative history of Title IX and noting this heightened deference point). See
also infra notes 65–69 and accompanying text (further discussing the modern legal basis for heightened
deference in this context).
7. See Jennifer Hahn, Schoolgirl Dreams, M
S. MAG., Fall 2007, at 46.
8. M
ARY WOLLSTONECRAFT, A VINDICATION OF THE RIGHTS OF WOMAN (1792).
9. Yale Will Admit Women in 1969; May Have Coeducational Housing, H
ARV. CRIMSON (Nov. 15,
1968), https://www.thecrimson.com/article/1968/11/15/yale-will-admit-women-in-1969/ [hereinafter
Yale Will Admit Women in 1969].
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 71
coeducation.”
10
The utter lack of seriousness with which the matter was discussed
among otherwise respectable people and institutions belied its significance for
women. But it appears to have been in line with the administration’s rationale for
the policy change, which was reported more-or-less consistently by the rival
schools’ newspapers. According to The Crimson, President Brewster denied that a
“student-sponsored Coed Week [which] brought women students from
throughout the northeast for academic and social activity . . . had a direct effect on
his decision, but his proposal to the faculty praised the organizers of the week and
their guests for providing Yale with ‘uncommon excitement.’”
11
The Yale Daily
News noted that “the decision to have women in 1969 was based not on Yale’s
seeing her mission as the education of both sexes, but on fears that Yale cannot
continue to attract the nation’s top males to a non-coeducated campus.”
12
In this context, Title IX was very much an “idea revolution.”
13
It sought to
force colleges and universities to matriculate, educate, and graduate female
students not to service men and their institutional needs, but on an equal basis
with their male students. It required them to see women as they saw men: as
students and as alumni without regard to their sex; and to own sex equality in all
respects as one of their own institutional goals.
The transition wasn’t always smooth, but with some notable exceptions,
mostly today colleges and universities have fully embraced these ideas. Indeed,
as we write this almost fifty years later, although their numbers are still
disproportionately low in STEM fields and in leadership positions in the
professional ranks, women have become the majority of college graduates.
14
As a
result, they are an increasingly important part of the work force and the
economy.
15
Title IX was not singularly responsible for these developments, of
course, but the statute’s role in the larger societal project that is sex equality, and
specifically the empowerment of women and girls, is widely recognized and
celebrated.
16
This narrative is generally mirrored in the context of education-based sport.
High schools, colleges, and universities understand that the education of women
10. A Timeline of Women at Yale, YALE U., https://celebratewomen.yale.edu/sites/default/files/
files/Timeline-of-Women-at-Yale.pdf (last visited Dec. 1, 2019) (quoting N.Y.
TIMES). This is not an
isolated example of the sexism on display in the paper in that period. See also, e.g, Faith A. Seidenberg,
The Federal Bar v. The Ale House Bar: Women and Public Accommodations, 5 V
AL. U. L. REV. 318, 324–25
(1971) (noting that “The New York Times, in reporting the . . . story [of Seidenberg v. McSorleys’ Old Ale
House, Inc., 317 F. Supp. 593 (S.D.N.Y. 1970) (holding that bar violated Equal Protection Clause when it
refused to admit women as patrons)], said, ‘There was, perhaps a trace of wistfulness in the ruling
[that] the sawdust-floored haven was just another “public place” that must admit any customer who
comes in, even a woman.’” N.Y.
TIMES, June 26, 1970, at 1.).
11. Yale Will Admit Women in 1969, supra note 9.
12. A Timeline of Women at Yale, supra note 10.
13. Musil, supra note 1, at 42 (quoting Professor Sadker).
14. Dani Matias, New Report Says Women Will Soon Be Majority of College-Educated U.S. Workers,
NPR (June 20, 2019), https://www.npr.org/2019/06/20/734408574/new-report-says-college-educated-
women-will-soon-make-up-majority-of-u-s-labor-f.
15. Id.
16. See, e.g., Hogshead-Makar & Zimbalist, supra note 2.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
72 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
and girls includes providing them with opportunities both to participate and to
compete that are on par with those that are provided to boys and men. As is the
case in STEM, the numbers are not equal, and schools often struggle to achieve
their regulatory obligations.
17
Still, “[s]ince the enactment of Title IX, women’s
participation in sport has grown exponentially.
18
In high school, girls’
participation numbers have grown from 294,000 in 1971–72 to more than 3.4
million in 2018-19.
19
In college, women’s numbers have grown from 30,000
20
in
1972 to more than 288,000
21
in 2017–18. Women and girls today have the
opportunity only boys and men had in the previous period to reap the widely
recognized and highly valued benefits of being physically strong, of being on
teams and developing the myriad skills associated with competitive sport, of
attending college on athletic scholarships, and of high-end competitive
experiences.
22
Again, although Title IX is not singularly responsible for these
developments, it is generally credited with a central role in this aspect of the
empowerment project.
23
There is an important difference between the two stories, however. Where
there has been a clear and steady upward trajectory for women and girls in
academics, especially outside of STEM, in athletics the momentum has always
been mixed, and it has been a constant battle to gain and to retain ground.
24
Among other things, the “fate” of women’s sports “has always been tied to the
larger political climate.”
25
Because of this, and because of the recency in historical
time of the broader commitment to sex equality, it is important for those who are
devoted to the idea to remain attuned to shifts in that climate.
The earliest and most persistent political opponents of women’s sports came
from the broader football community and from men’s sport more generally.
26
Whatever they thought about women’s equality in theory, they were clear that it
17. See Gerald Gurney, Donna Lopiano & Andrew Zimbalist, Chapter 6: A Continuing Disgrace:
Discrimination Based on Gender, Race, Ethnicity, and Disability, in U
NWINDING MADNESS: WHAT WENT
WRONG WITH COLLEGE SPORTS AND HOW TO FIX IT (2017).
18. This Day in History: Title IX Enacted, H
ISTORY (July 28, 2019), https://www.history.com/this-
day-in-history/title-ix-enacted [hereinafter This Day in History].
19. 2018-19 High School Athletics Participation Survey, N
ATL FEDN OF STATE HIGH SCH. ASSNS 50,
54 (2019), https://www.nfhs.org/sports-resource-content/high-school-participation-survey-archive/.
20. This Day in History, supra note 18.
21. The Equity in Athletics Data Analysis Cutting Tool, OFFICE OF POSTSECONDARY EDUC., U.S. DEPT
OF EDUC., http://ope.ed.gov/athletics (last visited Feb. 29, 2020).
22. See infra notes 128–147 and accompanying text (detailing this point).
23. See, e.g., This Day in History, supra note 18.
24. This aspect of the story is routinely emphasized in Title IX retrospectives. See, e.g., Hogshead-
Makar & Zimbalist, supra note 2, at 5–6 (summarizing “the struggle for gender equity in athletics”).
25. S
USAN WARE, TITLE IX: A BRIEF HISTORY WITH DOCUMENTS, 13 (2007). Interestingly, the
explanations for the relative weakness of sport and STEM may be similar or the same, i.e., a lack of
commitment on the part of original stakeholders to seeing females succeeding in those areas in
particular, together with related sex-linked stereotypes and cultural norms. The numbers and
experiences are better in medical school and medicine, which our co-author Michael Joyner suggests
may be related to the higher likelihood of predictability, promotion, and success in that STEM field.
26. See Hogshead-Makar & Zimbalist, supra note 2; infra note 41 and accompanying text.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 73
should not come at the expense of existing men’s programs. In addition to resisting
the threshold assumption that Title IX should apply to sport, they have specifically
resisted the integration of teams, the inclusion of men’s revenue producing sports
in spending comparisons, and the reallocation of spending from men’s programs
to fund women’s programs. Throughout, the underlying premise has been that
men’s sport produces higher value social goods and thus should not be
diminished in an effort to achieve different goods that are of lesser or questionable
value.
The most recent political challenge has come from the identity movement and
affiliated advocacy groups whose goal has been to secure much needed
protections for people who are transgender. To that end, movement advocates
have pushed for policy reforms that would grow the circumstances in which law
is sex-blind. Where sex remains a basis for classification, they have worked to
ensure that people who are transgender are included in spaces and programming
consistent with their gender identity.
27
The merits of both approaches are clear to us in contexts where sex does not
actually matter. But in sport, where sex and the sex-linked physical traits
associated with the male and female body are outcome determinative, the effects
of the proposed reforms would be revolutionary: they would require either the
dismantling of Title IX’s existing sex-segregated architecture and thus of the
female category, or the unconditional inclusion of males who identify as females
in girls and women’s sport.
28
While the latter is less obviously existential than the
former, both would signal that policymakers were abandoning the original
commitment to sex equality in this setting.
There is no question about this, as the goal is expressed, unambiguously, in
the public statements of movement advocates; for example, in this one from a set
of prominent civil rights organizations dedicated to ensuring, among other things,
that Title IX evolves to disallow any distinctions on the basis of sex as “sex” is
normally defined:
[W]e support laws and policies that protect transgender people from
discrimination, including in participation in sports, and reject the suggestion that
cisgender [sex typical] women and girls benefit from the exclusion of women and
girls who happen to be transgender.
29
27. Doriane Lambelet Coleman, Sex in Sport, 80 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS 63, 102–111 (2017).
28. We understand that language and word choices are fraught in this discussion. We explain our
approach and vocabulary immediately below, at and around notes 31–37. The bottom line is that our
goal is to communicate to a broad audience in a highly contested space, including about what sex is
and how it is relevant. To do this well, we can’t adopt an unfamiliar or unclear lexicon, or one that
assumes a particular political outcome since this paper is in part about what that outcome should be.
We know this will make some readers uncomfortable, but we hope that this explanation will help. We
intend no disrespect.
29. Statement of Women’s Rights and Gender Justice Organizations in Support of Full and Equal Access
to Participation in Athletics for Transgender People, NAT. WOMENS LAW CTR. (Apr. 10, 2019), https://
nwlc.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/04/Womens-Groups-Sign-on-Letter-Trans-Sports-4.9.19.pdf
[hereinafter Statement of Women’s Rights and Gender Justice Organizations].
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
74 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
The underlying premise of those who support this move to elide the relevant
physical differences between females on the one hand, and males who identify as
women and girls on the other, is that reconceiving of sex as gender identity—or
privileging gender identity over sex—will produce the highest value overall.
30
The goals of this paper are to provide the legal, factual, and normative
background necessary to evaluate the merits of this most recent challenge to the
sports exception to Title IX’s general nondiscrimination rule, and then to present
the case for re-affirming the exception in a form that is appropriate for this next
period of its history. It proceeds in three parts as follows: Part I describes the legal
history of Title IX’s sports exception, its goals, and the current state of the legal
doctrine. Part II explains its scientific basis and rationale. Part III sets out the best
case for and against affirming the commitment to sex equality in education-based
sport, and then presents our argument for resolving the collision of interests at
issue. The paper concludes that the original “idea revolution” continues to do
important work and should not be abandoned, including in the sports space where
equality requires not only recognizing but also celebrating physical sex
differences. Including trans people within this design is difficult by definition, but
because they are also entitled to dignity and respect, policymakers should accept
the challenge.
* * *
Standardizing vocabulary is critical to communication among the different
groups concerned with this topic. Many do not use the same words and phrases,
and even if they do, they often use them differently. Most difficult are those
instances when a word or term that is important to one group for descriptive or
political reasons is politically anathema or even painful to another. Because
capturing and controlling language is part of movement strategy, solving the latter
impasse is especially complicated. We have attempted to standardize our use of
the language in a way that avoids unnecessary harm or discomfort, but to the
extent we cannot always do this, we intend no disrespect. Our goal is to
communicate to a broad audience using standard terms, not to demean.
31
Most importantly, given current debates, we do not work from the
assumption that sex is or includes gender identity. Whether “sex” in law includes
or is distinct from “gender identity” is at issue in both the debates about H.R. 5,
The Equality Act (2019),
32
and in the Title VII case currently pending in the United
30. See, e.g., id. (arguing that it is good for all women that transgender women and girls are
included in the category “women” including in athletics competition on the basis that there are no
cognizable differences among transwomen and females that are not “driven by stereotypes and fear . . .
nondiscrimination protections for transgender people—including women and girls who are
transgender—are not at odds with women’s equality or well-being, but advance them”). For an
analysis of this claim from our perspective, i.e., from a different feminism, see infra notes 184–193 and
accompanying text.
31. For a set of up-to-date working definitions from medicine and endocrinology, see Joshua D.
Safer & Vin Tangpricha, Care of Transgender Persons, 381 N
EW ENG. J. MED. 2451, 2451–60 (2019).
32. Earlier versions of H.R. 5 distinguished “sex” from “gender identity” where the current bill
defines “sex” to include “gender identity.” See Equality Act, H.R. 5, 116th Cong. (2019). This drafting
move is based in evolving views in the advocacy and biosciences communities about how gender
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 75
States Supreme Court.
33
The related question whether gender identity is
biologically based and, if so, whether it should be considered an aspect or
characteristic of biological sex is the subject of ongoing consideration by relevant
experts in the scientific community.
34
For now, however, both remain contested
claims in a context in which “sex” is otherwise understood to be the word we use
to denote the individual’s biological and reproductive classification as male or
female.
35
Because this paper is precisely about whether policy should be reformed
so that sex in this standard sense comes to be replaced by or to include gender
identity in the context of education-based sport, it is necessary for us clearly to
distinguish the operative terms. Again, we intend no disrespect.
Sex – Biological sex. “Either of the two divisions, designated female and male, by
which most organisms are classified on the basis of their reproductive organs and
functions.”
36
The cluster of sex-linked traits—i.e., chromosomal, gonadal,
endocrinological (hormonal), and phenotypic characteristics—commonly used to
establish and denote sex. Primary and secondary sex characteristics. Although
they are terms of art and commonly used in science and medicine, “biological sex
and “biological (fe)male” may be hurtful to those who are triggered by references
to sexed bodies. Because sport relies on the biological distinction between males
and females to justify separate sex sport, however, we need to use the terms in
their scientific sense and to consider their substance in this discussion.
37
Again,
we intend no disrespect.
identity is appropriately characterized and also how best to craft a political path to full equality and
inclusion.
33. Equal Emp’t Opportunity Comm’n v. R.G. & G.R. Harris Funeral Homes Inc., 884 F.3d 560
(6th Cir. 2018).
34. See Safer & Tangpricha, supra note 31, at 2451–52 (addressing this point). For a summary
description of some of the ongoing work on “brain sex” more generally, see also Coleman, Sex in Sport,
supra note 27, at 75–77.
35. See, e.g., R (on the Application of Miller) v. College of Policing & Chief Constable of
Humberside, [2020] EWHC 225 (Admin) [225], ¶ 267 (Eng.) (decision out of the United Kingdom’s
High Court of Justice, addressing this contested issue and the expert witness statement of Professor
Kathleen Stock on the point that “For many English speakers, ‘woman’ is strictly synonymous with
‘biologically female[‘] and ‘man’ with ‘biologically male’.”).
36. Sex, A
M. HERITAGE DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE (5th ed. 2020).
37. One of our co-authors, Michael Joyner, is a biomedical researcher who, in the 2000s, was
admonished in the peer review process to use the phrase “sex differences” and not “gender
differences” when describing biological phenomenon. This insistence is increasingly routine in the
biomedical setting where the study of sex differences is now well established and producing important
value both in the basic sciences and in applications in personalized medicine. For example, there is a
journal dedicated to the subject, see
BIOLOGY OF SEX DIFFERENCES, https://bsd.biomedcentral.
com/about/ (last visited Feb. 15, 2020); and the federal government routinely emphasizes this focus in
its own work and in the distribution of research funding. See, e.g., U.S.
FOOD & DRUG ADMIN.,
Understanding Sex Differences at FDA (Apr. 12, 2019), https://www.fda.gov/science-research/womens-
health-research/understanding-sex-differences-fda. This focus is in part the result of the report from
the N
ATL. ACAD. OF SCI. INST. OF MED., EXPLORING THE BIOLOGICAL CONTRIBUTIONS TO HUMAN
HEALTH: DOES SEX MATTER? (2001) [hereinafter EXPLORING THE BIOLOGICAL CONTRIBUTIONS],
http://www.nationalacademies.org/hmd/~/ media/Files/Report%20Files/2003/Exploring-theBiological-
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
76 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
Female—An individual whose sex is female, i.e., who has ovaries not testes and a
natural estrogenic not androgenic endocrine system. A person’s designation as
“female” may not correspond with their gender identity (in the case of a trans
person) or their sex recorded at birth (in the case of some intersex persons).
Male—A person whose sex is male, i.e., who has testes not ovaries and a natural
androgenic not estrogenic endocrine system. A person’s designation as “male”
may not correspond with their gender identity (in the case of a trans person) or
their sex recorded at birth (in the case of some intersex persons).
Sex stereotype—An assumption (which may be evidence-based or not) or a
generalization (which may have a factual basis) about the aptitudes, preferences,
and capacities of males and females based on their biological sex.
Gender—Social and cultural expression of masculine or feminine behavior. Often
used differently as a synonym for biological sex.
Gender identity—A person’s deeply held internal sense of themselves as male,
female, both, neither, or fluid, and which can be different from their biological sex
or their sex recorded at birth.
Trans—Transgender—Gender incongruent—The word or term used to describe a
person whose gender identity is different from their biological sex or their sex
recorded at birth.
Trans(gender) woman/girl or man/boy—A person who is trans(gender) who
identifies as a woman/girl or man/boy.
I. T
HE LEGAL HISTORY, MISSION, AND CURRENT DOCTRINE
Title IX was developed to secure equality for women and girls in federally
funded educational settings. It filled the gap that was left by Title VII of the 1964
Civil Rights Act, which protects against sex discrimination in employment but
excludes educational settings otherwise, and by Title VI, which prohibits federally
funded programs from discriminating on the basis of race, color, and national
origin, but not on the basis of sex. Because of this gap, there was no federal
statutory remedy to address the educational disparities women and girls
experienced in relation to boys and men before Title IX. There was also no effective
constitutional remedy to address laws that supported sex discrimination, as the
Contributions-to-Human-Health-Does-Sex-Matter/DoesSexMatter8pager.pdf (explaining the
difference between sex and gender (identity), reporting on the extensive physiological processes and
medical contexts in which “sex matters”, and because of this indicating, among other things, the need
for researchers to address “the inconsistent and often confusing use of the terms “sex” and “gender”
in the scientific literature and popular press”).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 77
United States Supreme Court had yet to subject them to more than rational basis
scrutiny.
38
As described in the Introduction, the architects of Title IX settled on a hybrid
approach to achieving sex equality in education. They paired a general, sex-blind
non-discrimination rule with a set of limited, sex-affirmative exceptions, which
allow educational institutions to take sex into account where doing so is necessary
to address particular imbalances, i.e., in admissions, in programming, and in sport.
In sport, at least, if an institution can meet its sex equality obligations using a sex-
blind approach—without taking sex into account—it need not use these sex-
affirmative tools; they are formally permissive not mandatory. But they become
mandatory in effect if these obligations are not or cannot be met otherwise.
39
Assurances that sports teams would be sex segregated were material to Title
IX’s passage and to congressional approval of its implementing regulations.
40
For
38. See Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190 (1976) (holding for the first time that sex discrimination was
subject to heightened, i.e., intermediate, scrutiny under the Constitution’s Equal Protection Clause).
39. As it concerns sports, this requirement is clear in the statute’s legislative history, in the original
1975 regulations, and in the original 1979 Policy Interpretation. See Regulations of the Department of
Education, Nondiscrimination on the Basis of Sex in Education Programs or Activities Receiving
Federal Financial Assistance, 34 C.F.R. §106.12 (regulations governing athletics); Title IX of the
Education Amendments of 1972; The Policy Interpretation: Title IX and Intercollegiate Athletics, 44
Fed. Reg. 71,419 (Dec. 11, 1979) (again making clear the requirement of parity of competitive
opportunities). For example, the 1979 Policy Interpretation provides, inter alia, as follows:
4. Application of the Policy—Selection of Sports.
In the selection of sports, the regulation does not require institutions to integrate their
teams nor to provide exactly the same choice of sports to men and women. However,
where an institution sponsors a team in a particular sport for members of one sex, it
may be required either to permit the excluded sex to try out for the team or to sponsor
a separate team for the previously excluded sex.
a. Contact Sports—Effective accommodation means that if an institution sponsors a
team for members of one sex in a contact sport, it must do so for members of the other
sex under the following circumstances:
(1) The opportunities for members of the excluded sex have historically been limited;
and
(2) There is sufficient interest and ability among the members of the excluded sex to
sustain a viable team and a reasonable expectation of intercollegiate competition for
that team.
b. Non-Contact Sports—Effective accommodation means that if an institution sponsors
a team for members of one sex in a non-contact sport, it must do so for members of the
other sex under the following circumstances:
(1) The opportunities for members of the excluded sex have historically been limited;
(2) There is sufficient interest and ability among the members of the excluded sex to
sustain a viable team and a reasonable expectation of intercollegiate competition for
that team; and
(3) Members of the excluded sex do not possess sufficient skill to be selected for a single
integrated team, or to compete actively on such a team if selected.
In this context “skill” is understood to include physical not just learned capacity. See infra notes 40–54
and accompanying text. Together with the original 1975 regulations, the 1979 Policy Interpretation is
woven into the fabric of Title IX, including in statutory law. See infra notes 51–69 and accompanying
text (elaborating on the Title IX scheme).
40. As the bill made its way through Congress, “[a] few people (very few) noticed that athletics
might be affected . . . and so there was a discussion on the floor of the Senate about whether [it] required
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
78 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
different reasons, both men’s and women’s groups supported and/or insisted on
this. Men’s teams simply did not want to have to include females on their rosters
or to be made to subsidize the equality project.
41
Women’s groups wanted separate
opportunities because they were keen to secure equality in education-based
sports, and they understood that it couldn’t be achieved without this separation.
In particular, women and women’s groups fell into one of two camps. Both
accepted that there was a performance gap between male and female athletes that
necessitated sex segregation and thus a sports exception to Title IX’s general non-
discrimination rule. But they disagreed about the source of the gap and thus about
the terms of the exception:
One group took the position that sex segregation and thus the sports
exception in the regulations would be necessary only for a period, until females
were afforded the (equal) training and competition opportunities that would be
required eventually to close the performance gap; after that, sport could be co-ed.
42
educational institutions to allow women to play on football teams.” WARE, supra note 25, at 41. The
answer from its floor manager Senator Birch Bayh was no. Id. “Having inserted that notion into the
legislative history, higher education retreated.” Id. That brief discussion on the Senate floor was
significant in two respects: it presaged the decades-long resistance to Title IX that would come from
college football and men’s sport in general. See supra note 26 and accompanying text (summarizing this
resistance), and infra note 41 and accompanying text (further describing the legislative and regulatory
history). And it laid the necessary legal foundation for sex segregation in this setting. The “sports
exception” or “carve out” to Title IX’s prohibition on sex discrimination in federally funded educational
settings powered girls’ and women’s sport and continues to secure its success today.
41. See supra note 26 and accompanying text. The sports question exploded in the aftermath of
the bill’s passage through Congress. From the time President Richard Nixon signed the Education
Amendments into law in the summer of 1972 to the summer of 1975 when Congress formally approved
the implementing regulations, the institutional powerhouse that is men’s college football went into
overdrive to ensure that, in fact men’s teams would not have to accommodate female athletes, and that
equality for female athletes would not come at the expense of men’s revenue producing sports. This
activity was particularly heated in 1974 and 1975. In that period, the Senate heard but ultimately
declined to pass a bill sponsored by Senator John Tower (R-TX) to amend Title IX to exclude revenue
producing sports from compliance tabulation. Had it succeeded, this would have meant that spending
on female athletes and women’s sports programs could be only be compared with spending on men’s
non-revenue producing sports, simultaneously insulating (primarily) men’s football and basketball
programs from Title IX’s effects, and reducing schools’ obligations to women’s programs. Instead,
Congress passed an alternative bill sponsored by Senator Jacob Javitz (R-NY), formally the Educational
Amendments of 1974, which required the Secretary of the Department of Health, Education, and
Welfare (HEW) to develop “with respect to intercollegiate athletic activities reasonable [regulations]
concerning the nature of particular sports.” The Education Amendments of 1974, Pub. L. 93–380, 88
Stat. 612. Although some advocates for mens sport continued to press the point that men’s revenue
producing sports should not be made to pay (either directly or indirectly) for women’s programming,
the Department’s focus during this rulemaking process was mainly on the question whether men’s and
women’s sport and teams would be sex segregated. Comments and lobbying from men’s groups were
consistently against integration. The NCAA, for example, had no interest in having Title IX cover sport
at all, and it was opposed to including women in any of its programming.
42. The National Organization for Women (NOW) originally disagreed with the AIAW and the
NCAA that the goal should be separate sex sport. In a letter to President Ford, HEW Secretary Casper
Weinberger explained NOW’s position that “the ‘separate but equal’ concept is inappropriate for any
civil rights regulation and that open access should be required for all athletic teams with one exception.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 79
In general, one might characterize advocates in this first group as holding the view
that sex differences were entirely the result of disparate treatment and sex
stereotypes, both of which could be eradicated over time. In their view, like the
classroom, eventually sport could also be sex-blind. The language they used in
this context is reminiscent of that which appears in cases involving race-based
affirmative action measures.
43
The other group took the position that the performance gap was the result of
a combination of disparate treatment, sex stereotypes, and biological differences.
For those in this second group, even if that part of the performance gap that was
the result of disparate treatment and sex stereotype could be eradicated, sex
segregation would always be necessary because immutable biological differences
would remain.
44
This view is consistent with the Supreme Court’s current
substantive equality jurisprudence, which distinguishes sex from stereotype, but
also race from sex on the ground that the latter but not the former involve inherent
differences—these differences are properly considered when doing so serves to
empower rather than to subordinate.
45
Importantly, although textualists reject the role of legislative history in
statutory interpretation, to the extent that it remains important to others, and that
there is an ongoing debate about what policymakers meant when they used the
word “sex” in the drafting period,
46
it is easily resolved in the sports setting. At
least in this context, the legislative history is clear that “sex” meant biological sex,
which was distinguished from sex stereotype. Specifically, the biological
When women are effectively excluded from open teams (where skill in the given sport is the criteria, it
is still conceded by all that open competition for a tackle football team would result in an all-male
team), separate teams should be provided for them on the basis that the training and sports
traditionally available to women have been limited and the provision of separate teams until such time
as the training gap is filled would best fulfill the purposes of the Act.” See Letter from Caspar
Weinberger, supra note 5, at A-6, A-7.
43. See, e.g., Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 306 (2003) (“We expect that 25 years from now, the use
of racial preferences will no longer be necessary to further the interest [in student body diversity]
approved today.”).
44. See Kathleen Megan, Transgender Sports Debate Polarizes Women’s Advocates, CT
MIRROR (July
22, 2019), https://ctmirror.org/2019/07/22/transgender-issues-polarizes-womens-advocates-a-conundr
um/ (quoting our co-author Donna Lopiano: “Title IX was passed 47 years ago to ensure an equal
education for girls, but included a ‘carve out’ allowing separate programs for girls because of the clear
biological advantage that males have over females in athletics. ‘It was the notion that there are distinct
biological differences in sex that are immutable.’”); Memorandum from Patricia Sullivan Lindh, the
President’s Special Assistant for Women’s Programs, to James Cannon, White House Domestic Policy
Advisor (May 1, 1975) (on file with the Gerald R. Ford Presidential Library) (noting that allowing
schools to field only one “open” team would let them off the hook in terms of providing equal
opportunities for women, and that to assure sex equality, schools should have to take into account
differences between men and women in “competitive skill and physical ability”).
45. See, e.g., United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515, 532–33 (1996).
46. See, e.g., Brief of Walter Dellinger, et al. as Amici Curiae in Support of the Employees, Bostock
v. Clayton County, GA, Altitude Express, Inc. v. Zarda, and Harris Funeral Homes, Inc. v. Stephens,
888 F.3d 100 (Nos.17-1618, 17-1623,18-107), 2019 WL 3027045; Brief for the Federal Respondent
Supporting Reversal, Harris Funeral Homes, Inc. v. EEOC, et al., 884 F.3d 560 (No.19-107) (debating
this question in the context of Title VII of the 1964 Civil Rights Act).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
80 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
differences between males and females that account for the performance gap, as
well as those sex traits and related customs that raised safety and privacy concerns,
were key to the discussions and decisions around inclusion and segregation.
47
Similarly, to the extent that there is debate today about whether Title IX was
designed to ensure that girls and women were able not only to participate but also
to compete on an equal basis with boys and men, the legislative history also
confirms this commitment. While some early proponents of the statute suggested
that females were or should be interested only in (“cooperative and inclusive”)
participation not (“patriarchal capitalist”) competition,
48
the stereotypes and
47. The hearings throughout the month of June 1975, before the House of Representatives
Subcommittee on Post-Secondary Education of the Committee on Education and Labor, are illustrative,
including in that members and witnesses distinguished race from sex, and focused on the extent to
which the performance gap was the result of inherent differences between the sexes rather than
historical disparate treatment. See Sex Discrimination Regulations: Hearings Before the Subcomm. on Post-
Secondary Educ. of the Comm. of Educ. & Labor, 94th Cong. 54 (1975) (statement of Bob Blackman, Head
Football Coach, Univ. of Illinois) (“HEW has already [taken sex differences into consideration], they
have already stated . . . that because of physiological differences between men and women, the women
are not expected to compete in the so-called contact sports . . . . So they have already stated the fact that
there are differences.”); id. at 130 (statement of Joan Holt, President, Eastern District, Ass’n for
Intercollegiate Athletics for Women) (“[W]e have been discriminated against in the past due to
physiological limitations that women do have, we are not capable of getting a place on the men’s team,
and they then have an obligation, both because of the discrimination of the past and because of our
competitive interests, that they would have to provide a separate team for the women in this case.”);
id. at 197 (statement of Rep. McKinney) (“We know that until puberty, girl and boy children have
roughly the same athletic capacity. After this point there is a significant difference in their ability in
most sports. However, until we stop punishing girl children for being tomboys and allow their full
participation in scholastic athletics, we will never know their true capacity as sportspersons.”); id. at
390 (statement of Bernice Sandler, Dir., Project of the Status and Educ. of Women & Exec. Assoc., Ass’n
of Am. Colls.) (“In almost all other areas of discrimination, the precedents and principles developed by
the courts in race discrimination cases can readily and easily be applied to sex discrimination problems.
Because of the general physical differences between men and women as a whole, the principles
developed in other discrimination areas do not easily fit athletic issues, particularly in the area of
competitive sports, where the issue of single sex and integrated teams is a difficult one to solve.
‘Separate but equal,’ which is a discredited legal principle in terms of civil rights, may have some
validity when applied to some areas of competitive athletics . . . .”); id. at 339 (“Before puberty, males
and females are nearly identical in their physical abilities. Tests of strength, muscular endurance,
cardiovascular endurance and motor performance show few differences between the sexes up to this
age. Beyond that age, however, the male becomes considerably stronger, possesses greater muscular
and cardiovascular endurance and is more proficient in almost all motor skills.”); id. at 343 (“To some,
complete integration of the sexes in all sports would appear to be both the simplest and the least
discriminatory solution. Upon closer examination, however, it becomes clear that because of the
differences in training and physiology, such an arrangement would effectively eliminate opportunities
for women to play in organized competitive athletics. For these reasons, this alternative would not
appear to be in line with the principle of equal opportunity.”); id. (“[T]he ‘separate-but-equal’ principal
in competitive athletics can be justified for sex discrimination (but not for race discrimination) because
there are general physical differences between [women] and men (but not between blacks and
whites).”).
48. See Interview with our co-author Donna Lopiano, Adjunct Professor of Sports Mgmt., S. Conn.
State Univ. (Oct. 13, 2019) (describing the views of some within the “old” NOW and the AIAW who
rejected NCAA-style sports administration and competition). This approach to women’s sport is
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 81
norms they advanced were rejected by other advocates and ultimately by
lawmakers.
49
To use a currently topical distinction, education-based sport was not
designed to be like selection for the military’s special forces, where women are
entitled to participate in selection rounds but are rarely, if ever, competitive for
full status because of their physical disadvantages relative to men;
50
rather, sport
was sex segregated because the goal was parity across all categories of
opportunity.
The regulations that were formally presented to, reviewed, and passed over
by Congress in 1975 mimic Title IX’s hybrid approach, and reflect the general
consensus at the time regarding sex segregation in sport. Specifically, they begin
with this general nondiscrimination provision:
86.41(a) General. No person shall, on the basis of sex, be excluded from
participation in, be denied the benefits of, be treated differently from another
person or otherwise discriminated against in any interscholastic … athletics
offered by a recipient, and no recipient shall provide any such athletics separately
on such basis.
51
The provision is followed by the exception, or “carve out,” for sex-segregation in
sport. The exception emphasizes the two factors that make sex segregation
described in Ann Travers, The Sport Nexus and Gender Injustice, 2 STUD. IN SOC. JUST. 79, 86 (2008)
(describing “radical and cultural feminist . . . scholars [who] indict sport in its current patriarchal
capitalist iteration and seek to replace it with cooperative and nonhierarchical celebrations of
physicality and play based on feminist principles of cooperation and inclusion”).
49. D
EPT OF EDUC., OFFICE FOR CIVIL RIGHTS, A POLICY INTERPRETATION: TITLE IX AND
INTERCOLLEGIATE ATHLETICS (1979) (making clear the requirement of parity of competitive
opportunities); McCormick ex rel. McCormick v. Sch. Dist. of Mamaroneck, 370 F.3d 275, 282 (2d Cir.
2004) (recognizing the difference between the opportunity to participate and the opportunity to
compete for the win, including for championships, and holding that Title IX requires schools to provide
females with opportunities in both categories that are on par with those provided to males). Notably,
when the subject is not trans athletes or (intersex) athletes with differences of sex development, the
premise that sex segregated sport exists in part to ensure that there are the same numbers of spots in
finals and on podiums for females as for males is generally not controversial. Indeed, even their
advocates tend to take this as a given, i.e., they appear to appreciate the benefits, including for their
clients, of sex segregation. This has them arguing not for co-ed sport, but rather for what is in effect an
exception for those whose sex is male but who identify legally and/or personally as women and girls.
See, e.g., Statement of Women’s Rights and Gender Justice Organizations, supra note 29 (arguing that
“transgender women and girls” should benefit fully and equally from participation “in women’s
sports”); Doriane Lambelet Coleman, Semenya and ASA v. IAAF: Affirming the Lawfulness of a Sex-Based
Eligibility Rule for the Women’s Category in Elite Sport, 19 S
WEET & MAXWELLS INTL SPORTS L. REV. 83
(detailing how a version of this approach was presented in Ms. Semenya’s case at CAS) [hereinafter
Coleman, Semenya and ASA v. IAAF] .
50. Meghann Myers, A Female Soldier Has Made It Through the Army’s Special Forces Selection, A
RMY
TIMES (Nov. 14, 2018), https://www.armytimes.com/news/your-army/2018/11/14/a-female-soldier-has-
made-it-through-the-armys-special-forces-selection/.For more information on the integration of
women into special operations career fields and concerns about sex equality and sex specific or neutral
standards in that highly competitive context, see K
RISTY M. KAMARCK, CONG. RESEARCH SERV., R42075,
WOMEN IN COMBAT: ISSUES FOR CONGRESS (2016), https://fas.org/sgp/crs/natsec/R42075.pdf.
51. 34 C.F.R. § 106.41 (a) (2019).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
82 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
necessary for the attainment of equality in sport, that is, concerns about
competitive fairness and physical safety:
86.41(b) Separate teams. A recipient may operate or sponsor separate teams for
members of each sex where selection for such teams is based upon competitive
skill or the activity involved is a contact sport. However, where a recipient
operates or sponsors a team in a particular sport for members of one sex but
operates or sponsors no such team for members of the other sex, and athletic
opportunities for members of that sex have previously been limited, members of
the excluded sex must be allowed to try-out for the team offered unless the sport
involved is a contact sport. For purposes of this part, contact sports include
boxing, wrestling, rugby, ice hockey, football, basketball and other sports the
purpose or major activity of which involved bodily contact.
52
As is the case with Title IX more generally, the affirmative approach is permissive,
not mandatory, in the first instance, meaning that if a school can find a way to
provide equal training and competition opportunities for females without taking
sex into account, they can proceed in a sex-blind way; but if proceeding in a sex-
blind way perpetuates disparities, the affirmative approach becomes mandatory.
53
According to Susan Ware, “[i]n the early days of the law, much discussion
centered on whether teams should be coeducational based on skill (the model
adopted in elementary and high school physical education classes) and whether
women should be eligible to play on mens teams. On the high school and
intercollegiate level, a consensus soon emerged that sex-segregated but
comparable sports teams were a better model.”
54
As our co-author Donna Lopiano
has explained, “[i]t was the notion that there are distinct biological differences in
sex that are immutable . . . Everybody agreed that . . . if you have boys and girls
competing after puberty, who would be more likely to get on a team? Who would
win? It would be men. There would be very few women.”
55
From 1975 through 1988, proponents of girls’ and women’s sport continued
to face resistance from boys and men and the male sports establishment, including
with respect to funding, facilities, coaching staff, and competition opportunities.
56
52. Id. § 106.41 (b).
53. See, e.g., Yellow Springs Exempted Village School Dist. Bd. Of Educ. v. Ohio High School
Athletic Ass’n, 647 F.2d 651, 656 (6th Cir. 1981) (Title IX “grant[s] flexibility to the recipient of federal
funds to organize its athletic program as it wishes [one or separate teams] so long as the goal of equal
athletic opportunity is met.”).
54. W
ARE, supra note 25, at 5. This model—co-ed “prior to puberty”— is represented in the still-
current position of the Women’s Sports Foundation (WSF). See W
OMENS SPORTS FOUND., ISSUES
RELATED TO GIRLS AND BOYS COMPETING WITH AND AGAINST EACH OTHER IN SPORTS AND PHYSICAL
ACTIVITY SETTINGS, https://www.womenssportsfoundation.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/08/issues-
related-to-girls-and-boys-competing-with-and-against-each-other-in-sports-and-physical-activity-sett
ings-the-foundation-position.pdf [hereinafter
WOMEN SPORTS FOUND., ISSUES RELATED TO GIRLS AND
BOYS COMPETING]. Although the original position paper was developed and published several years
ago, the WSF re-affirmed it on August 14, 2019. See id.
55. Megan, supra note 44 (quoting Donna Lopiano).
56. See Hogshead-Makar & Zimbalist, supra note 2, at Part III (describing this period as “The
Initial Backlash”); Mary C. Curtis & Christine Grant, Landmark Title IX Cases in History, G
ENDER EQUITY
IN
SPORT, http://bailiwick.lib.uiowa.edu/ge/historyRE.html (listing key dates in the resistance).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 83
This resistance was particularly fierce in circumstances that involved cuts to boys’
and men’s programs that were considered—or described as—necessary to meet
Title IX requirements.
57
It culminated in the 1984 decision, Grove City College v.
Bell, in which the United States Supreme Court sided with the Reagan
Administration’s position that Title IX and its sex equality requirements applied
only to the particular programs that received federal funds, not more broadly to
the institutions of which they were a part.
58
Because the federal government did
not contribute directly to education-based sports programs, Grove City in effect
“gutted” Title IX.
59
As a result, the merits of the “idea revolution”—that there
should be sex equality across educational settings including in education-based
sport—were once again put to Congress.
60
The Education Amendments of the Civil Rights Restoration Act of 1987 were
finally passed in 1988, over President Reagan’s veto, extending Title IX’s sex
equality requirements to all programs within institutions receiving federal funds.
61
As Title IX expert and three-time Olympic Gold Medalist Nancy Hogshead-Makar
explains, although sport was not prominent in the legislative history prior to the
statute’s passage in 1972, “sports for girls and women were the driving narrative
behind the imperative to pass the law again in 1988. Sports for women swung
Republicans and average families.”
62
Since then, although resistance has been
ongoing,
63
the legislative, executive, and judicial branches of the federal
government have consistently reaffirmed at least the essential aspects of the
statutory scheme, including that parity of competitive opportunities matter and
that the original regulations remain an integral part of the law.
64
57. Cases involving cuts to boys’ and men’s wrestling were particularly prevalent. See generally
Bradley David Ridpath et al., Changing Sides: The Failure of the Wrestling Community’s Challenges to Title
IX and New Strategies for Saving NCAA Sport Teams, 1 J.
INTERCOLLEGIATE SPORT 255 (2008). See, e.g.,
Nat’l Wrestling Coaches Ass’n v. Dep’t of Educ., 366 F.3d 930 (D.C. Cir. 2004) (affirming district court’s
finding that the decision to drop wrestling is a matter of institutional preference not a requirement in
fact or in effect of Title IX).
58. Grove City College v. Bell, 465 U.S. 555 (1984) (rejecting Association’s challenge to Title IX
Policy Interpretation).
59. See E-mail from Nancy Hogshead-Makar, Chief Exec. Officer, Champion Women, to Doriane
Lambelet Coleman, Professor of Law, Duke Law Sch. (Feb. 19, 2020, 3:17 PM) (on file with authors).
60. See supra note 13 and accompanying text (introducing “the idea revolution”).
61. See S. 557 (100th): Civil Rights Restoration Act of 1987, 100th Cong. (1987), https://www.
govtrack.us/congress/bills/100/s557 (providing timeline of the history and text of the legislation).
62. See E-mail from Hogshead-Makar, supra note 59. See also W
ARE, supra note 25, at 36–43
(describing this history).
63. See Hogshead-Makar & Zimbalist, supra note 2, at Part V (describing the period from 2001 to
2008 as “The Second Backlash”).
64. For example, the 1994 Equity in Athletics Disclosure Act requires “co-educational institutions
of postsecondary education that participate in a Title IV, federal student financial assistance program,
and have an intercollegiate athletic program, to prepare an annual report to the Department of
Education on athletic participation, staffing, and revenues and expenses, by men’s and women’s teams.
The Department . . . use[s] this information in preparing its required report to the Congress on gender
equity in intercollegiate athletics.” Equity in Athletics Disclosure Act, U.S. DEPT. OF EDUC. (Jan. 24, 2017),
https://www2.ed.gov/finaid/prof/resources/athletics/eada.html. The data in detail are available from
The Equity in Athletics Data Analysis Cutting Tool, OFFICE OF POSTSECONDARY EDUC., U.S. DEPT OF
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
84 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
Although the legislative veto was declared unconstitutional in 1983,
65
in 1984,
the United States Supreme Court affirmed that “where Congress has specifically
delegated to an agency the responsibility to articulate standards governing a
particular area”—as it did in 1972 with respect to Title IX’s standards governing
athletics—“we must accord the ensuing regulation considerable deference.”
66
The
standards in the 1975 Regulations as well as their 1979 Policy Interpretation have
continued to benefit from such protection, even as the Court has increasingly
rejected the use of legislative history as a tool for statutory interpretation.
67
In part,
EDUC., http://ope.ed.gov/athletics. In McCormick ex rel. McCormick v. Sch. Dist. Of Mamaroneck, 370 F.3d
275, 282 (2d Cir. 2004), the Second Circuit held that a school district was out of compliance with Title
IX when it established separate boys’ and girls’ teams but provided boys with more and more
important competitive opportunities. And in 2016, the Obama Administration issued guidance for the
inclusion of transgender student-athletes in education-based sports that made clear its commitment to
sex segregation when this remains necessary to secure competitive fairness and physical safety. See
infra note 73 and accompanying text (providing the details of this guidance).
65. INS v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919, 959 (1983).
66. Kelley v. Bd. of Trs., 35 F.3d 265, 270 (1994) (citing Chevron, U.S.A., Inc. v. Nat. Res. Def.
Council, Inc., 467 U.S. 837 (1984)).
67. In 2018, the Eastern District of Michigan explained that heightened deference under Chevron
is accorded to both the 1975 Regulations and the 1979 Policy Interpretation of the 1975 Regulations
“because Congress explicitly delegated to the agency the task of prescribing standards for athletic
programs under Title IX.” See Mayerova v. E. Mich. Univ., 346 F. Supp. 3d 983, 989 (E.D. Mich. 2018)
(citing the First Circuit’s decision in Cohen v. Brown Univ., 991 F.2d 888, 895 (1st Cir. 1993) and the
Sixth Circuit’s decision in Miami Univ. Wrestling Club v. Miami Univ., 302 F.3d 608, 615 (6th Cir.
2002)). See also Ollier v. Sweetwater Union High Sch. Dist., 768 F.3d 843, 855 (9th Cir. 2014) (affirming
its practice of giving Chevron deference to the 1979 Policy Interpretation and applying it to the high
school setting, citing the Second Circuit’s decision in Mamaroneck, 370 F.3d at 300, and the Sixth Circuit’s
decision in Horner v. Ky. High Sch. Athletic Ass’n, 43 F.3d 265, 272–75 (6th Cir. 1994)); Biediger v.
Quinnipiac Univ., 691 F.3d 85, 96–97 (2d Cir. 2012) (the Second Circuit reaffirming its decision in
Mamaroneck); Mansourian v. Regents of Univ. of Cal., 602 F.3d 957, 965 (9th Cir. 2010) (the Ninth Circuit
reaffirming that “both the Policy Interpretation and the Clarification are entitled
to deference under Chevron”).
Chevron was reaffirmed by the Court itself in 2013, in City of Arlington v. FCC, 569 U.S. 290 (2013)
(Justice Scalia writing for the Court and noting that courts cannot substitute themselves as
policymakers when this is precisely the job of the federal agencies). City of Arlington was a 6/3 decision,
with Justices Roberts, Kennedy, and Alito in dissent. Their concern was the extension of what they
describe as essentially legislative authority to the executive—and to the consequent creation of an ever-
growing administrative state—even in circumstances where Congress did not clearly delegate this
authority. Id. at 312 (Roberts, C.J., dissenting). In their view, “before a court may grant such deference,
it must on its own decide whether Congress—the branch vested with lawmaking authority under the
Constitution—has in fact delegated to the agency lawmaking power over the ambiguity at issue.” Id.
at 317. Unless Chevron itself is repealed, because Congress “explicitly delegated to the agency the task
of prescribing standards for athletic programs under Title IX,” both the 1975 Regulations and the 1979
Policy Interpretation should continue to be accorded heightened deference by the courts. Mayerova, 346
F. Supp. 3d at 989. Of course, this would not be the case should Title IX, the Regulations, and/or the
Policy Interpretation be repealed.
The final deference point relates to the Department of Education’s own ongoing interpretation
of the 1975 Regulations and the 1979 Policy Interpretation. Such interpretations are afforded regular—
not heightened—deference only when the standards themselves are “genuinely ambiguous” and: the
agency’s interpretation is (1) its own “‘authoritative’ or ‘official position,’” (2) “reasonable”; (3)
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 85
this is because the Regulations and Policy Interpretation establish the architecture
of and rationale for sex segregated education-based sport; and, they are embedded
in an inextricably linked web of related law, including in statutory law. For
example, the 1994 Equity in Athletics Disclosure Act (EADA) requires federally
funded colleges and universities to produce annual reports regarding their athletic
programs so that the Department of Education can monitor compliance with Title
IX.
68
The fact that there is deep bipartisan support for girls and women’s sport
surely influences ongoing deference to the regulations as well.
69
To date, the movement to include trans people in spaces and opportunities
based on their gender identity rather than on their sex has not altered this legal
state of affairs at the federal level. That is, as of this writing, there are no new
regulations that require recipients of federal education dollars to include
transgender people in sport on the basis of their gender identity rather than their
biological sex; and there are no federal cases that expand the meaning of “sex” to
include or to be replaced by “gender identity” in a Title IX sports context.
70
As
they have done under Title VII, a few federal circuits have expanded the meaning
of “sex” under Title IX, but so far only in the contexts of restrooms and locker room
access.
71
Supporters of transgender student-athletes have argued that these
precedents are applicable to sport: that just as transgender girls must be permitted
to use girls’ restrooms they must also be permitted to be on girls’ sports teams and
included without condition in girls’ competitions.
72
But as the Obama
“implicate[s] its substantive expertise”; and (4) “reflect[s] ‘fair and considered judgment.’” Kisor v.
Wilkie, 139 S. Ct. 2400, 2412, 2415–17 (2019) (explaining that deference to agencies under the Court’s
decision in Auer v. Robbins, 519 U.S. 452 (1997), are based in the presumption that “when granting
rulemaking power to agencies, Congress usually intends to give them, too, considerable latitude to
interpret the ambiguous rules they issue” but that courts need not defer to those interpretations when
they are not justified according to these requirements).
68. See supra note 64 (discussing the EADA).
69. This bipartisan support for girls and women’s sport, in a climate where such issues are often
difficult to find, is presumably one of the reasons Republicans have seized on trans inclusion in girls
and women’s sport as an election issue for the 2020 cycle. See, e.g., James Freeman, Opinion, Did
Democrats Just Create a Problem with Soccer Moms and Dads? A Friday House Vote Could Be the Sleeper Issue
of 2020, W
ALL ST. J. (May 20, 2019, 4:56 PM), https://www.wsj.com/articles/did-democrats-just-create-
a-problem-with-soccer-moms-and-dads-11558385818.
70. As of this writing, the first federal case to address this issue has just been filed in the United
States District Court in the District of Connecticut. See Soule et al. v. Conn. Interscholastic Athletic
Conference et al., No. 3:20-cv-00201, (D. Conn., filed Feb. 12, 2020). Otherwise, a Westlaw search of the
All Federal database for “Title w/1 IX & transgender & sport” yields only thirteen cases, none of which
apply to selection for sex segregated sports teams. Almost all are bathroom and/or locker room privacy
cases. The others are not even indirectly on point.
71. See, e.g., Adams ex rel. Kasper v. Sch. Bd. of St. Johns Cty., 318 F. Supp. 3d 1293 (M.D. Fla.
2018) (restrooms); G.G. ex rel. Grimm v. Gloucester Cty. Sch. Bd., 822 F.3d 709 (4th Cir. 2016), vacated
and remanded, 137 S. Ct. 1239 (2017) (restrooms); Johnston v. Univ. of Pittsburgh, 97 F. Supp. 3d 657
(W.D. Penn. 2015) (restrooms and locker rooms).
72. See, e.g., Shayna Medley & Galen Sherwin, Banning Trans Girls from School Sports Is Neither
Feminist Nor Legal, ACLU (Mar. 12, 2019, 5:45 PM), https://www.aclu.org/blog/lgbt-rights/transgender-
rights/banning-trans-girls-school-sports-neither-feminist-nor-legal (arguing that “[w]hen
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
86 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
Administration apparently recognized in 2016 when it was interpreting Title IX in
its Transgender Guidance to schools, sport is different from restrooms not only in
its policy objectives but also in the extent to which sex actually matters:
73
Where
sport is designed to develop and showcase the capacities of the physical body—
including mental control of the physical body, and the girls’ and women’s
categories are designed to secure sex equality with respect to the benefits that flow
from sports, restrooms are designed to provide a space for people to relieve
themselves, and girls’ and women’s restrooms are designed to secure safety and
privacy as they do.
74
In law, at least, institutional design and objectives matter, as
do the facts about whether individuals are similarly or dissimilarly situated with
respect to the characteristics that are relevant to their attainment. In any event, the
Trump Administration has withdrawn the Obama Guidance, restoring the
original regulatory status quo;
75
and the Department of Education’s Office of Civil
Rights is investigating a complaint alleging that the Connecticut Interscholastic
misinformation about biology and gender is used to bar transgender girls from sports in schools
receiving federal funds, it amounts to the same form of sex discrimination that has long been prohibited
under Title IX”); Dave Zirin, Transphobia’s New Target Is the World of Sports: First It Was Bathrooms, Now
It’s Athletics, N
ATION (Mar. 5, 2019), https://www.thenation.com/article/archive/trans-runner-daily-
caller-terry-miller-andraya-yearwood-martina-navratilova (analogizing the two in general).
73. Dear Colleague Letter on Transgender Students from Catherine E. Lhamon, Assist. Sec’y for
Civil Rights, U.S. Dep’t of Educ. & Vanita Gupta, Principal Deputy Assist. Att’y Gen. for Civil Rights,
U.S. Dep’t of Justice (May 13, 2016), https://www2.ed.gov/about/offices/list/ocr/letters/colleague-
201605-title-ix-transgender.pdf. Compare
Restrooms and Locker Rooms. A school may provide separate facilities on the basis of sex,
but must allow transgender students access to such facilities consistent with their gender
identity.
A school may not require transgender students to use facilities inconsistent with
their gender identity or to use individual-user facilities when other students are not required
to do so. A school may, however, make individual-user options available to all students who
voluntarily seek additional privacy.
with
Athletics. Title IX regulations permit a school to operate or sponsor sex-segregated athletics
teams when selection for such teams is based upon competitive skill or when the activity
involved is a contact sport. A school may not, however, adopt or adhere to requirements that rely
on overly broad generalizations or stereotypes about the differences between transgender students and
other students of the same sex (i.e., the same gender identity) or others’ discomfort with transgender
students. Title IX does not prohibit age-appropriate, tailored requirements based on sound,
current, and research-based medical knowledge about the impact of the students’
participation on the competitive fairness or physical safety of the sport.
Id. at 3 (emphasis added). The first and third sentences in the “Athletics” paragraph are original to the
regulations. The second or middle sentence is guidance developed by the administration concerning
the application of the traditional rule to the transgender context. The administrations position at least
on the first and third points, but arguably also the second, was well-grounded in the legislative history
as recognized over the years by the courts interpreting the statute and its regulations. See, e.g., Kelley
v. Bd. of Trs., 35 F.3d 265, 270 (7th Cir. 1994) (noting that “Congress itself recognized that addressing
discrimination in athletics presented a unique set of problems not raised in areas such as employment
and academics”).
74. The difference between sport and restrooms is further detailed in Coleman, Sex in Sports, supra
note 27, at nn.316–317 and accompanying text.
75. Andrew Mytelka, Trump Administration Rescinds Obama-Era Guidance on Transgender Students,
C
HRON. OF HIGHER EDUC. (Feb. 22, 2017), https://www.chronicle.com/blogs/ticker/trump-administrati
on-rescinds-obama-era-guidance-on-transgender-students/117025.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 87
Athletic Conference (CIAC) policy allowing unconditional inclusion of trans girls
in girls competition violates Title IX.
76
Regardless of the Trump Administrations motivation for taking up this
complaint,
77
as a doctrinal matter it is on sound footing. Not only is the legal
history of the sports exception to Title IX’s general nondiscrimination rule clear
that it is focused on equality for females in relation to males, but it is also generally
accepted that sex segregated sport is constitutional because of its grounding in the
“inherent [biological] differences between men and women” and because its
purposes are to “compensate” women (and girls) for past and ongoing sex-related
discriminations, to “promote equal [sports] opportunity [between men and
women],” and to “advance full development of [women’s and girls’] talent and
capacities.”
78
As we explore further below, if both “sex” and “gender identity”
became the basis for eligibility for girls’ and women’s sport—or, as applied, if both
girls’ and boys’ sport included both males and females—inherent differences
would no longer be the rationale for separate sex sport, and the girls and women’s
categories would no longer serve their equality and empowerment goals. They
would lose their constitutional grounding.
II. T
HE SCIENTIFIC EVIDENCE SUPPORTING THE SPORTS EXCEPTION
The disagreement among women and women’s groups in the 1970s about
whether sex differences in athletic ability were merely stereotype or in fact
inherent has long since been resolved. In 2008, Gina Kolata of The New York Times
reported that “even though some scientists once predicted that women would
eventually close the gender gap in elite performances—it was proposed that all
they needed was more experience, better training and stronger coaching—that
idea is . . . largely discredited, at least for Olympic events.”
79
As we write this paper
in 2020, it is clear that Kolata’s point is accurate across the board, at both the elite
and non-elite levels of almost all standard sports and events. To say, as some
advocacy groups do, that there isno evidenceor that it ismyth and
76. Dan Brechlin, Federal Office of Civil Rights Agrees to Investigate Connecticut’s High School
Transgender Athlete Policy, H
ARTFORD COURANT (Aug. 8, 2019), https://www.courant.com/sports/high-
schools/hc-sp-high-school-connecticut-transgender-policy-20190808-20190808-
j5yfbovklvf4fjrir4ouybssj4-story.html.
77. Mark Joseph Stern, Betsy DeVos May Force High Schools to Discriminate Against Trans Athletes,
SLATE (Aug. 9, 2019), https://slate.com/news-and-politics/2019/08/trump-education-department-title-
ix-trans-athletes-discrimination.html (noting that this decision may be part of a broader anti-trans
agenda).
78. Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 67–70 (quoting United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515,
532 (1996)); see also Kelley v. Bd. of Trs., 35 F.3d 265, 272 (7th Cir. 1994) (upholding the constitutionality
of the statute and regulations against an equal protection challenge on these grounds); Cohen v. Brown
Univ., 991 F.2d 888, 900–01 (same).
79. Gina Kolata, Men, Women and Speed. 2 Words: Got Testosterone? N.Y.
TIMES (Aug. 22, 2008),
https://www.nytimes.com/2008/08/22/news/22iht-22testosterone.15533354.html; see also Robinson
Meyer, We Thought Female Athletes Were Catching Up to Men, but They’re Not, A
TLANTIC (Aug. 9, 2012),
https://www.theatlantic.com/technology/archive/2012/08/we-thought-female-athletes-were-catching-
up-to-men-but-theyre-not/260927/.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
88 D
UKE
J
OURNAL
O
F
G
ENDER
L
AW
&
P
OLICY
Volume 27:69 2020
“outdated stereotype”—that males, including trans women and girls not on gender
affirming hormones, are “better” in sport than females is simply to deny science.
80
Sporting opportunities are not always identical, but there is now substantial
parity in training and competition, especially at the elite level, and this has resulted
in important performance gains for female athletes. But as the following figure by
our co-author Mike Joyner tracking marathon performances illustrates, better
training, better races, and more competitive opportunities throughout the world
have resulted in gains for both sexes with a compressed time frame for women.
Marathon World Record Progression
The upshot is that today, depending on the sport and event, the gap between the
best male and female performances remains somewhere between 7 to 25 percent;
and even the best female is consistently surpassed by many elite and non-elite
males, including both boys and men.
81
If elite sport were co-ed or competition were
open, even the best female would be rendered invisible by the sea of men and boys
80. See, e.g., Medley & Sherwin, supra note 72 (using the terms “myth”, “stereotype” and the claim
of “no research” to describe the biological evidence in this context); Emilie Kao, How Pelosi’s “Equality
Act” Would Ruin Women’s Sport, H
ERITAGE
F
OUND
. (Apr. 24, 2019), https://www.her
itage.org/gender/commentary/how-pelosis-equality-act-would-ruin-womens-sports (quoting Sunu
Chandy from the National Women’s Law Center using these ACLU talking points).
81. For data comparing male and female performances in a number of events on the track,
including the number of males (boys and men) who surpass the very best females, see, e.g., Doriane
Lambelet Coleman &Wickliffe Shreve, Comparing Athletic Performances: The Best Elite Women to Boys and
Men, D
UKE
C
TR
.
FOR
S
PORTS
L
AW
&
P
OL
Y
(2018), https://law.duke.edu/sites/default/files/cente
rs/sportslaw/comparingathleticperformances.pdf.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 89
who would surpass her. As this next visual using the 400 meters on the track
reflects, in percentage terms, the best female is bettered by relatively non-elite boys
and men starting at 0.01 percent.
82
Simulating the final 100 meters of that event, it
shows three of the fastest ever females on their very best day, against the
thousands of boys and men whose performances—just in the single year 2017—
would be competitive with or better than them in that final stretch.
Comparing the Best Elite Females to Boys & Men:
Personal Bests For 3 Female Gold Medalists vs 2017 Performances by Boys & Men
The same is true outside of the professional ranks in education-based sport,
including in high school regular and post-season competition. For example, in
2016, Vashti Cunningham—the daughter of former NFL quarterback Randall
Cunningham—set the high school American record in the high jump outdoors at 6
feet, 4½ inches. Since she joined the professional ranks, she has jumped 6 feet,
inches, and is ranked in the top ten in the world.
83
Still, in just one year—2018—
and just in the state of California, 50 high school boys jumped higher than her high
school best. Nationwide, in 2019, 760 boys jumped higher.
84
As the following
figure simulating a high jump competition demonstrates, if high school sport were
co-ed or competition were open, Cunningham would not have made it to her state
82. Jeff Wald, Doriane Lambelet Coleman, Wickliffe Shreve & Richard Clark, Comparing the Best
Elite Females to Boys and Men: Personal Bests for 3 Female Gold Medalists Versus 2017 Performances by Boys
and Men, D
UKE CTR. FOR SPORTS LAW & POLY (2018).
83. Athlete Profile: Vashti Cunningham, W
ORLD ATHLETICS, https://www.iaaf.org/athletes/united-
states/vashti-cunningham-280887 (last visited Jan. 15, 2020).
84. See 2019 High School Men’s High Jump Rankings, A
THLETIC.NET, https://www.athletic.net/Tra
ckAndField/Division/Event.aspx?DivID=97967&Event=9&page=7.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
90 D
UKE
J
OURNAL
O
F
G
ENDER
L
AW
&
P
OLICY
Volume 27:69 2020
meet, she would not be on the national team, and we would not know her name
other than as a footnote on her father’s Wikipedia page.
85
High Jump: Best American Boys in 2019
Compared to the Girls’ American Record
It is perhaps more important for policy purposes that those girls who are only
average high school athletes—for example, those who might just or occasionally
win an invitational event or regional competition—would fare even worse.
Indeed, a review of age-group performance data confirms what policymakers
understood already in the 1970s: if sport were not sex segregated, most school-
aged females would be eliminated from competition in the earliest rounds.
86
The
following chart illustrates this point, using California intra-state regional results
from the 2019 outdoor season, where the best boy in the state jumped 7 feet, 0
inches, and the best girl jumped 5 feet, 10 ½ inches. The average differential was
85. This figure by Jeff Wald is based on data from Athletics.net. According to that database and
that of the N
AT
L
F
ED
N OF
S
TATE
H
IGH
S
CH
.
A
THLETIC
A
SS
NS
, https://www.nfhs.org/RecordBook/
Record-book-result.aspx?CategoryId=1712 (last visited Jan. 28, 2020), only five other females residing
and competing in the U.S. have jumped in this range: Alyxandria Treasure (1.92 meters in 2017),
Jeannelle Scheper (1.91 meters in 2016), Toni Young (1.93 meters in 2009), Amy Acuff (1.91 meters in
1992), and Latrese Johnson (1.90 meters in 1985).
86. See supra notes 44, 54–55 and accompanying text (discussing this concern as it arose in the
original policymaking process). See also E-mail from Michael J. Joyner, Caywood Professor of
Anesthesiology and Perioperative Med., Mayo Clinic Sch. of Med., to Doriane Lambelet Coleman,
Professor of Law, Duke Law Sch. (Oct. 6, 2019, 9:08 AM) (on file with authors) (“My younger boys 9
and 7 are good swimmers and they are in mixed races and it is hit or miss boy or girl who wins. The
best swimmer in the club is a tall skinny 16-year-old girl who is getting recruited by good schools. She
has real ability. She gets crushed by guys who will swim D3 if they choose to.”); Coleman, Sex in Sport,
supra note 27, at n.173 (describing the experience in Massachusetts with boys at the girls’ state
swimming championships).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 91
approximately 12 inches. In percentage terms, across the state the performance gap
ranged from 11.88 percent to 20.73 percent.
2019 California Regional High Jump Results
87
The point that from puberty on, co-ed competition relegates most, if not all,
females to being only participants in the game is easiest to prove in the case of
sports with objective metrics, but “it is well-understood that a version of this story
can be told across the board, almost no matter the event.”
88
Indeed, the
performance gap is so well-understood, and so abundantly documented in easily
searchable databases, that it’s difficult to take seriously the claim that it is merely
87. We developed this chart using data from the query “California High Jump Results,” in
A
THLETIC.NET , https://www.athletic.net/ (last visited September 25, 2019).
88. Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 91; Robinson Meyer, We Thought Female Athletes Were
Catching Up to Men, but They’re Not, supra note 79.
REGION BEST BOY BEST GIRL % DIFFERENCE
Central
2.0828 1.778 14.63%
Central Coast
1.9812 1.6764 15.38%
Los An
g
eles
1.8796 1.5748 16.22%
N
orth Coast
2.0828 1.651 20.73%
N
orthern
1.9558 1.6764 14.29%
Oakland
1.8034 1.4732 18.31%
Sac-Joa
q
uin
2.032 1.73355 14.69%
San Die
g
o
2.032 1.7907 11.88%
San Francisco
1.8288 1.4732 19.44%
Southern
2.1336 1.7399 18.45%
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
92 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
“myth” and “false stereotype.”
89
Indeed, many on the sport and science side of the
discussion have not bothered to try.
90
Beyond the data, the sex-specific biology underlying the performance gap is
also well-studied and well documented. Like other scientific fields that have
focused on biological sex differences and that have come to recognize the extensive
(beyond reproductive) reach of sex in the human body,
91
sports science and related
disciplines—e.g., cardiology, hematology, endocrinology—have advanced
tremendously in their understanding of the bases for the sex differences in athletic
performance. What is clear from the evidence is that “the differences aren’t the
result of boys and men having a male gender identity, more resources, better
training or superior discipline. It’s because they have androgenized bodies.”
92
Specifically, scientists agree that “males and females are materially different with
respect to the main physical attributes that contribute to athletic performance,”
and that “the primary reason for sex differences in these attributes is exposure in
gonadal males to much higher levels of testosterone (T) during growth and
development (puberty), and throughout the athletic career.”
93
Before the onset of puberty, males and females produce similar, low levels of
T, that is, on the order of 0.25 milligrams (mg) per day. But starting at puberty,
male testes begin to produce much more than female ovaries and adrenal glands
combined. On average, males (including elite male athletes) produce about 7 mg
per day, and females (including elite female athletes) continue to produce about
0.25 mg per day. The normal male range is from 7.7 to 29.4 nmol/L. The normal
89. For example, domestic databases like Athletics.net provide not only national coverage but
also regional, state, and local coverage that goes deep into college, high school, junior high school, and
age group results. And international databases run by the governing bodies do a version of the same
on a global level. See supra notes 81–83 (providing data from the IAAF’s interactive database).
Nevertheless, in this period the ACLU regularly insists that there is “no evidence” that males are better
than females in sport. And even the NWLC publicly repeats this “no evidence” claim and adds that
all sex differences are “unfounded stereotype.” See supra note 80 and accompanying text (citing to these
talking points). It is only if one accepts their predicate that the category “women” includes males who
identify as female—or, as they put it, “women who happen to be transgender”—that stereotype theory
works in the sports space. See Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 105–106, 109–11 (describing and
responding to these rhetorical claims as they relate to sport). Otherwise, their argument is either
uneducated or convenient science denial. See Doriane Coleman, Martina Navratilova & Sanya
Richards-Ross, Pass the Equality Act but Don’t Abandon Title IX, W
ASH. POST (Apr. 29, 2019),
https://www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/pass-the-equality-act-but-dont-abandontitleix/2019/04/29
/2dae7e58-65ed-11e9-a1b6-b29b90efa879_story.html?noredirect=on.
90. From statistics, for example, see, e.g., For Crying Out Loud 2019, Biology in Sports Matters,
S
TATHOLE SPORTS (Apr. 18, 2019), http://statholesports.com/for-crying-out-loud-2019-biology-in-sport
s-matters/.
91. See E
XPLORING THE BIOLOGICAL CONTRIBUTIONS, supra note 37 (IOM report examining the
evolving study of sex differences and making the case that barriers to knowledge about sex differences
must be eliminated).
92. Coleman & Shreve, supra note 81.
93. Various experts have recognized the impact of testosterone in athletic performance. The Role
of Testosterone in Athletic Performance, D
UKE CTR. FOR SPORTS LAW & POLICY (Jan. 2019) [hereinafter
Testosterone in Athletic Performance] (emphasis added), https://law.duke.edu/sites/default/files/centers/
sportslaw/Experts_T_Statement_2019.pdf.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 93
female range is from 0.06 to 1.68 nmol/L.
94
In other words, as the following figure
from Jonathon Senefeld and our co-author Michael Joyner shows, beginning at
puberty, testosterone distributes bi-modally and males (whether they are trans or
not) generally produce four to fifteen times more testosterone than females
(whether they are trans or not). Female T readings are represented in red, male T
readings in blue/purple.
Nationally Representative Data for Total Testosterone
for the U.S. Population Ages 6–35 Years
95
94. Females with polycystic ovaries (PCOS) may have levels upward of 4.8 nmol/L, and those
with with untreated congenital adrenal hyperplasia (CAH) may have levels that are higher than that.
But no healthy female, e.g., no elite athlete, has a natural T level above 5 nmol/L.
95. Jonathon W. Senefeld & Michael J. Joyner (2019). The data in the figure are from the National
Health and Nutrition Examination Survey (NHANES), a study of health of random sample of children
and adults in the United States. Using standard, validated clinical laboratory measurement tools
(isotope dilution liquid chromatography tandem mass spectrometry) the NHANES laboratory
precisely determined total testosterone of 4,229 girls/women and boys/men from ages 6 –35 years.
These data are collected biennially to create a longstanding, National database of normative data. Panel
A demonstrates the distribution of total testosterone concentration in children age 6–18 for each year
using a box-plot to show the 25th, 50th and 75th percentile scores of testosterone. The error bars
represent 3 standard deviations (SD) from the mean testosterone, and all outliers (greater or lesser than
3 SD from the mean) are marked using symbols. The girls (red colored box-plots and symbols) have a
~10-fold increase in testosterone (~3 ngdL
-1
to ~30 ngdL
-1
) that plateaus at 14 years. The boys (blue
colored box-plots and symbols) have a substantially greater increase in testosterone than girls, an
increase of over 100-fold (~4 ngdL
-1
to ~450 ngdL
-1
) that begins to plateau at 16 years. Testosterone
concentrations are high and steady after age 18 (during years of peak endurance), and the distribution
of testosterone for adults in this age range (19-35 years) are displayed in Panel B. This data set of over
1,400 samples from men and women shows the distribution curves from 99 percent of the data, with
upper and lower outliers (0.05 percent above and below the mean) removed. The narrow range of the
distribution for normative values for women (10-60 ngdL
-1
) is much smaller than the large range of
normative values for men (175-925 ngdL
-1
).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
94 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
As the next two figures demonstrate, this different exposure literally builds
the male body in the respects that matter for sport. Specifically, “compared to
biological females, biological males have greater lean body mass (more skeletal
muscle and less fat), larger hearts (both in absolute terms and scaled to lean body
mass), higher cardiac outputs, larger hemoglobin mass, (also both in absolute
terms and scaled to lean body mass), larger VO
2max (higher aerobic capacity) (also
both in absolute terms and scaled to lean body mass), greater glycogen utilization,
higher anaerobic capacity, and different economy of motion.”
96
The figure immediately below, from David Handelsman, shows that the
emergence of the performance gap in running, jumping, and swimming tracks the
rise in male T levels at puberty:
Sex Differences in Athletic Performance Coinciding with the Onset of Male Puberty:
Running, Jumping, and Swimming
97
96. Testosterone in Athletic Performance, supra note 93.
97. This figure is part of a series that was published by David J. Handelsman et al., Circulating
Testosterone as the Hormonal Basis of Sex Differences in Athletic Performance, 39 E
NDOCRINE REVS. 803–29
(2018), https://academic.oup.com/edrv/article/39/5/803/5052770/.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
R
E
-A
FFIRMING THE
V
ALUE OF THE
S
PORTS
E
XCEPTION
95
This final figure, from our co-author Michael Joyner and his colleague
Jonathon Senefeld, homes in on the swimming line. It confirms that pre-pubertal
children of both sexes are competitive for the win in co-ed events, with females
having some advantage in the six to eight-year-old age brackets. This—together
with the requirement of sex-blind approaches when these do not undermine
equality goals—is the basis for co-educational programming in elementary school
and some age-group competitions.
98
The figure also confirms that from the onset
of physical puberty to late adolescence, the competitiveness of females decreases
essentially to zero. This—together with the preference for sex conscious
approaches when these are necessary to meet equality goals—is the basis for
policies that separate males and females in athletic competition starting in middle
school and beyond.
99
Sex Differences in Swimming Performance by Age
100
98. See generally
W
OMEN
S
S
PORT
F
OUND
.,
I
SSUES
R
ELATED TO
G
IRLS AND
B
OYS
C
OMPETING
, supra
note 54 (describing the circumstances in which it is appropriate legally and scientifically to provide for
co-ed and sex segregated sports and physical activities).
99. See id. (preferring co-ed sport until puberty). Swimming provides a particularly powerful
example of the need for sex segregation in this context because the socio-cultural explanations for the
performance gap are neutralized if not eliminated. Women and girls have had significant competitive
opportunities in swimming that preceded Title IX, more girls participate in USA swimming than boys,
training is systematic, rigorous and mixed from an early age, and records are typically set under
standardized conditions. Additionally, swimmers typically come from resource rich homes where sex
differences in nutrition or access to medical care are unlikely.
100. Michael J. Joyner & Jonathon W. Senefeld, Sex Differences in Youth Elite Swimming, 14 P
LO
S
ONE 5 (2019). The data in the figure are from the top five swimming performances of all-time by US
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
96 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
The State of Connecticut is illustrative. It explains the applicability of these
science facts in the FAQs that accompany its public school health, fitness, and
performance standards:
101
Why do some standards for boys and girls differ?
Two factors must be taken into account when determining criterion-
referenced health standards: inherent physiologic differences between
genders, and differences in health risks between genders. Due to physiologic
and anatomic differences between the genders, there may be inherent
performance differences between boys and girls for a specific fitness
component. For example, differences in cardiac function and body
composition between adolescent boys and adolescent girls result in
adolescent boys, as a general rule, having a higher aerobic capacity than
adolescent girls. Specifically, if the minimum V̇O
2max for healthy girls is 28 ml.
kg-1. min-1 and for healthy boys, 32 ml. kg-1. min-1, setting the same standard
for both on the One-Mile Run Test would not be appropriate. In the case of
aerobic capacity, gender differences are taken into account, along with
existing data on health risks, in order to determine the standards. In addition
to physiologic differences, the two genders do not face the same health risks
during their growth. To reflect these differentiated health risks, the standards
are adjusted.
Why are some standards for boys and girls the same?
When there is no valid reason for expecting a difference in the performance
between boys and girls, the standards are the same. For example, young
children, particularly in Grades 1-6, do not always possess the physical and
physiological differences that appear as children approach puberty (Falls &
Pate, 1993). When this is true, the same standards may be used for both
genders.
Why are standards for aerobic endurance lower for girls than for boys?
Inherent gender-related differences in body composition and in hemoglobin
concentration cause aerobic capacity, referred to as VO2 max, for boys and
girls who have the same level of physical activity, to be different. The
differences prior to puberty are very small or nonexistent (for hemoglobin
swimmers for each 1-year age group from age 5 to 18 years, a database maintained and verified by
USA Swimming. These data are using long course, freestyle swimming performances. Panel A
demonstrates the sex difference in swimming performance across age (5–18 years). The sex difference
in negative (indicating faster performances by girls) until age 10 (no sex differences) and then the sex
difference markedly increases (faster boys) with a plateau at age 17. This plateau at ~8.5 percent
maintains steady until ~age 50. The black line is the mean sex difference, and the grey area is the 95
percent confidence interval. Panel B demonstrates that similar trends were observed for each major
freestyle swimming distance. Notably, the sex difference is largest in ‘sprint events’ (50, 100 and 200
m) and smallest in ‘endurance events’ (400, 800 and 1,500 m). Panel C is the legend for panel B. The y-
axis for panel C is sex difference (%).
101. C
ONN. STATE DEPT OF EDUC., CONNECTICUT PHYSICAL FITNESS ASSESSMENT: THIRD
GENERATION 12–13 (2019–2020), https://portal.ct.gov/-/media/SDE/Phys-Ed/CPFA----Test-Administrat
ors-Manual---2019.pdf?la=en.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 97
concentration), but they increase during puberty and adolescence. These
differences are linked in part to differences in the reproductive hormones. The
lower VO2 max in girls compared to boys with the same physical activity level
are not thought to be associated with increased health risk. The standards for
boys and girls reflect the different levels of VO2 max that are associated with
increased health risk in adults.
102
Notably, based on its interpretation of Connecticut anti-discrimination law, the
Connecticut Interscholastic Athletics Conference (CIAC) has taken a position that
is at odds with the state’s physical standards, that is, despite the science and
related policy, it permits trans girls—whether or not they were on gender
affirming hormones—to compete in girls’ events.
103
As a result, in the three year
period 2016 to 2019, two trans girls who would not have been successful, had they
competed in the boys’ division, won fifteen individual state championships in the
girls division.
104
It is this set of facts that is the basis for the federal Title IX
complaint that the United States Department of Education’s Office of Civil Rights
is currently investigating.
105
Apart from testosterone, different sex-linked factors and processes also
contribute to sex differences in athletic performance. What this means is that even
when trans women and girls use blockers and/or gender affirming hormones, male
legacy advantages remain if their therapy begins only after the onset of puberty.
106
These include—among others—different muscle mass, bone density, and airway
size.
107
Legacy advantages are more or less pronounced, depending on the age at
102. Id.
103. See infra note 104 and accompanying text (summarizing the results of CIAC policy).
104. In spring 2018, Terry Miller and Andraya Yearwood placed first and second at the 2018 Class
M State Championship in the girls’ 100 meters with times of 11.77 and 12.22, respectively. Miller broke
the meet record of 12.16 that was set in 1995. 2018 CIAC Spring Championships: Class M Outdoor Track,
CIAC
TOURNAMENT CENT., https://content.ciacsports.com/ot18m.shtml (last visited Jan. 28, 2020). The
top five finishers from the Class M meet go on to the State Open, which includes the top twenty-five
athletes in the state. Miller and Yearwood took 1st and 2nd place there too, with times of 11.72 and
12.29 respectively. See 2018 CIAC Spring Championships: Open Outdoor Track, CIAC
TOURNAMENT CENT.,
https://content.ciacsports.com/ot18o.shtml (last visited Jan. 28, 2020). Because they had only run 11.87
and 12.28 going into the State Championships, and the boys’ qualifying time was 11.84, neither would
have qualified for post-season competition had they been competing in the boys’ division. The top six
from the State Open represent Connecticut in the New England Championship, which Miller went on
to win as well. See 2018 New England High School Outdoor Track and Field Championships,
R
UNNERSPACE.COM, https://new-england-interscholastic-outdoor-championships.runnerspace.com/e
profile.php?do=info&event_id=5773&year=2018 (last visited Jan. 28, 2020).
105. See supra notes 76–77 and accompanying text (discussing this complaint).
106. Among other related questions, whether male legacy advantages are offset by disadvantages
associated with transition is the subject of ongoing inquiry, including by Joanna Harper and colleagues
at the University of Loughborough.
107. For an easy to follow description of sex differences in this category, see Yvonne van Dongen’s
interview with physiologist Alison Heather, Even Before Birth, Genetic Building Blocks Are Giving Athletes
Born Male a Massive Advantage Over Females, S
TUFF (July 21, 2019), https://www.stuff.co.nz/sport/other-
sports/114327152/even-before-birth-genetic-building-blocks-are-giving-athletes-born-male-a-massive-
advantage-over-females; see also, e.g., Paolo B. Dominelli et al., Sex Differences in Large Conducting
Airway Anatomy, J.
APPLIED PHYSIOLOGY (1985).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
98 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
which the person physically transitions, and Joanna Harper has cautioned that
they may be offset by the disadvantages associated with taking exogenous
hormones and performing in a male frame with female T levels.
108
Finally, legacy
advantages are more or less relevant to performance depending on the sport and
event. The latter is why, for example, track and field has taken the position that
winding down testosterone levels is an acceptable compromise, but power lifting
has not.
109
In contrast, despite the frequent contrary assertion from advocates for
unconditional transgender inclusion, there is no evidence that other physical
traits—such as height, wingspan, muscle fiber type, or lactic acid processing
ability, among others—are similarly determinative of outcomes in sport.
110
As our
co-author Doriane Coleman has written elsewhere,
[t]here is no characteristic that matters more than testes and testosterone. Pick your
body part, your geography, and your socioeconomic status and do your
comparative homework. Starting in puberty there will always be boys who can
beat the best girls and men who can beat the best women.
Because of this, without a women’s category based on sex, or at least these sex-
linked traits, girls and women would not have the chance they have now to
develop their athletic talents and reap the many benefits of participating and
winning in sports and competition.
111
Indeed, even scientists Ross Tucker and Eric Vilain, who are on record in support
of gender inclusive policies, have acknowledged that this is why “we separate men
and women into categories . . . we want women to be able to win some
competitions;”
112
and, “[w]ithout a women’s category” based on sex-linked traits,
“elite sport would be exclusively male.”
113
Because the traits that account for the
performance gap are in play starting at the onset of male puberty, the same would
be true of non-elite, education-based sport. To paraphrase them both, without a
girls’ category based on sex, or at least on sex-linked traits, education-based
108. Katherine Kornei, This Scientist is Racing to Discover How Gender Transitions Alter Athletic
Performance—Including Her Own, S
CI. MAG. (July 25, 2018, 9:00 AM), https://www.sciencemag.
org/news/2018/07/scientist-racing-discover-how-gender-transitions-alterathletic-performance-
including.
109. Compare W
ORLD ATHLETICS ELIGIBILITY REGULATIONS FOR TRANSGENDER ATHLETES, WORLD
ATHLETICS, http://www.athletics.org.tw/Upload/Web_Page/WA/Eligibility%20Regulations%20for%20
Transgender%20Athletes,%20.pdf, with
USA POWERLIFTING TUE COMMITTEE REPORT 2019, USA
POWERLIFTING,https://www.usapowerlifting.com/wp-content/uploads/2019/05/USA-Powerllifting-TU
E-Committee-Report-2019.pdf.
110. See Testosterone in Athletic Performance, supra note 93 (“No other endogenous physical or
physiological factors have been identified as contributing substantially and predominantly to [sex]
differences [in athletic performance].”).
111. Doriane Lambelet Coleman, Sex, Sport, and Why Track and Field’s New Rules on Intersex Athletes
are Essential, N.Y.
TIMES (Apr. 30, 2018), https://www.nytimes.com/2018/04/30/sports/track-gender-
rules.html.
112. Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 91 (quoting Eric Vilain).
113. Id. at 86 (quoting Ross Tucker).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 99
competitive sport would be mostly, if not exclusively, male. And so, if we want
females to win some competitions, we need to separate them.
114
III.
REAFFIRMING THE MISSION
IN LIGHT OF THE CHALLENGE FROM THE IDENTITY MOVEMENT
As we show in Parts I and II, the question presented by advocates for
unconditional inclusion of transgender athletes in girls and women’s sport is not
whether there is a difference between the male body and the female body that
justifies current Title IX policy; nor is it whether that policy supports sex
segregation in this arena. Rather, the question is the normative one whether, in
light of new attention to and growing knowledge about differences of sex
development and gender incongruence, we are and should remain committed to
equality for females in relation to males in the education-based sports space.
Specifically, is that aspect of the idea revolution that was equality for females still
viable, or should we be moving on to a new one that rejects the original focus on
sex so that we can be inclusive of individuals who are gender diverse?
The voices with the megaphone at the moment prioritize this new and
different revolution;
115
but in fact, feminists are split on this issue, as are
transgender people whether or not they are also feminists.
116
In this respect, the
dispute is as much “in the family”
117
as it is among traditional political
opponents.
118
Biological sex, sex equality, and sport are matters that mean a lot to
114. None of this is new to gym teachers and secondary school coaches, who have long used sex
specific performance charts both to assess physical health and development and to sort students for
competitive games and teams. See supra notes 101–102 and accompanying text (setting out the State of
Connecticut’s standards). Nor is it new to the military, which similarly uses sex specific standards for
initial inclusion into the armed services and for fitness reviews, and sex neutral standards in
circumstances where operational needs outweigh inclusion and equality concerns. See generally
KAMARCK, supra note 50.
115. See infra text and accompanying notes 177–190 (discussing the public positions taken by,
among other organizations, the ACLU, the National Women’s Law Center, and the Women’s Sports
Foundation).
116. Compare Shasta Darlington, Transgender Volleyball Star in Brazil Eyes Olympics and Stirs Debate,
N.
Y. TIMES (Mar. 17, 2018), https://www.nytimes.com/2018/03/17/world/americas/brazil-transgender-
volleyball-tifanny-abreu.html (including the views of Joanna Harper and Tifany Abreu), with Scott
Gleeson & Erik Brady, These Transgender Cyclists Have Olympian Disagreements on How to Define Fairness,
USA
TODAY (Jan. 11, 2011), https://www.usatoday.com/story/sports/olympics/2018/01/11/these-
transgender-cyclists-have-olympian-disagreement-how-define-fairness/995434001/ (comparing the
views of Rachel McKinnon with those of some of her female competitors).
117. See, e.g., Coleman, Navratilova, & Richards-Ross, supra note 89; Doriane Coleman, Who Is a
“Woman” in Sport, V
OLOKH CONSPIRACY (Mar. 11, 2019, 8:02 AM), https://reason.com/2019/03/11/who-
is-a-woman-in-sport/; Dave Zirin, Martina Navratilova is Expelled From an LGBTQ Advocacy Group Over
Transphobia Accusations, N
ATION (Feb. 25, 2019), https://www.thenation.com/article/martina-navratil
ova-athlete-ally-transphobia/.
118. See, e.g., Andrea Jones & Clare Hepler, Males Don’t Belong in Women’s Sports—Even If They
Don’t Always Win, H
ERITAGE FOUND. (Nov. 27, 2019), https://www.heritage.org/gender/
commentary/males-dont-belong-womens-sports-even-if-they-dont-always-win (one of a series of
commentaries on the subject by the foundation); Megan, supra note 44 (reporting on filing of a Title IX
complaint by the Alliance Defending Freedom).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
100 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
many people regardless of politics, and so many people are interested in the
conversation.
In this final part of the paper, we set out what we see as the most persuasive
arguments on both sides of this debate, and we offer a proposal for policy reform
that would simultaneously secure Title IX’s existing commitment to sex equality
and make clear policymakers’ authority to develop approaches to the inclusion of
gender diverse students in education-based sport that do not undermine that
commitment.
A. The Affirmative Case for Sex Equality in Sport
As we see it, the most persuasive argument for sex equality in sport,
including in competitive education-based sport, is the following:
Equality for females is a broadly-held commitment and a high value social
good. Extending this commitment to education-based sport is part and parcel of
securing this value for the individual females who are directly involved, for
related stakeholders, and for society more generally. Because of biological
(“inherent”) differences between males and females, this value cannot be achieved
if teams and events are not separated by sex. And, because of the way equal
protection doctrine has evolved, there is likely no different—other than sex-
based—rationale for segregated sport that is likely to survive constitutional
scrutiny: if the classifications “girls’ sport” and “women’s sport” were based on
gender identity rather than sex, they would be difficult if not impossible to sustain.
Thus, for both biological and legal reasons, unless society is prepared to forego the
benefits that flow from girls’ and womens sport, the classification must continue
to be based on sex, or at least on reproductive sex-linked traits.
1. Sex Equality is a High-Value Social Good
Both sex equality in general and empowering females in particular are
societal priorities. For example, here using the word “gender” as a synonym for
“sex” the United Nations Population Fund explains that:
Gender equality is intrinsically linked to sustainable development and is vital to
the realization of human rights for all. The overall objective of gender equality is a
society in which women and men enjoy the same opportunities, rights and
obligations in all spheres of life. Equality between men and women exists when
both sexes are able to share equally in the distribution of power and influence;
have equal opportunities for financial independence through work or through
setting up businesses; enjoy equal access to education and the opportunity to
develop personal ambitions, interests and talents; share responsibility for the
home and children and are completely free from coercion, intimidation and
gender-based violence both at work and at home.
Within the context of population and development programmes, gender equality
is critical because it will enable women and men to make decisions that impact
more positively on their own sexual and reproductive health as well as that of their
spouses and families. Decision-making with regard to such issues as age at
marriage, timing of births, use of contraception, and recourse to harmful practices
(such as female genital cutting) stands to be improved with the achievement of
gender equality.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 101
However it is important to acknowledge that where gender inequality exists, it is
generally women who are excluded or disadvantaged in relation to decision-
making and access to economic and social resources. Therefore a critical aspect of
promoting gender equality is the empowerment of women, with a focus on
identifying and redressing power imbalances and giving women more autonomy
to manage their own lives. This would enable them to make decisions and take
actions to achieve and maintain their own reproductive and sexual health. Gender
equality and women’s empowerment do not mean that men and women become
the same; only that access to opportunities and life changes is neither dependent
on, nor constrained by, their sex.
119
That males and females are physically different in relevant ways, and that
females are routinely subject to discrimination because of their distinct physical
characteristics, explains the UN’s commitment to an equality toolbox that includes
sex affirmative measures, that is, measures that “see” sex or that are not “sex
blind.” It is understood that such measures can be effective in ways that sex
neutral measures are not:
120
Taking gender concerns into account when designing and implementing
population and development programmes therefore is important for two reasons.
First, there are differences between the roles of men and women, differences that
demand different approaches. Second, there is systemic inequality between men
and women. Universally, there are clear patterns of women’s inferior access to
resources and opportunities. Moreover, women are systematically under-
represented in decision-making processes that shape their societies and their own
lives. This pattern of inequality is a constraint to the progress of any society
because it limits the opportunities of one-half of its population. When women are
constrained from reaching their full potential, that potential is lost to society as a
whole. Programme design and implementation should endeavour to address
either or both of these factors.
121
These principles are codified at the international level in, for example, the UN
Convention on the Elimination of Discrimination Against Women, and in
European Union law.
122
The goal to “[de]limit the opportunities of one-half of [the] population,” as
well as the utility of sex conscious approaches to achieving it, have been embraced
in the domestic context as well. In the United States, both the means and the ends
are supported by a constitutional standard that recognizes the fact of sex
differences and the distinction between sex and sex stereotype. The now-classic
119. Frequently Asked Questions About Gender Equality (FAQS), UNITED NATIONS POPULATION FUND,
https://www.unfpa.org/resources/frequently-asked-questions-about-gender-equality (last visited Jan.
28, 2020) [hereinafter Gender Equality FAQs] .
120. Mona Lena Krook & Diana Z. O’Brien, The Politics of Group Representation: Quotas for Women
and Minorities Worldwide, 42 C
OMP. POL. 253 (2010); Stephanie M. Wildman, Affirmative Action: Necessary
for Equality for All Women, 12 B
ERKELEY LA RAZA L.J. 429 (2000); Laurel Wamsley, California Becomes 1st
State To Require Women On Corporate Boards, NPR (Oct. 1, 2018), https://www.npr.org/2018/10/01/6533
18005/california-becomes-1st-state-to-require-women-on-corporate-boards.
121. Gender Equality FAQs, supra note 119.
122. See Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 68, n.17.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
102 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
articulation of this standard comes from Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg’s majority
opinion in United States v. Virginia:
123
While the law cannot “rely on overbroad generalizations about the different
talents, capacities, or preferences of males and females,” it “does not make sex a
proscribed classification.”
124
Indeed, it recognizes that “[p]hysical differences
between men and women . . . are enduring” and that these “‘[i]nherent differences’
. . . remain a cause for celebration, but not for denigration of the members of either
sex or for artificial constraints on an individual’s opportunity.”
125
As applied, this
means is that “[s]ex classifications may be used to compensate womenfor
particular economic disabilities [they have] suffered,’ to ‘promot[e] equal
employment opportunity,’ [and] to advance full development of the talent and
capacities of our Nation’s people”;
126
but, they may not be used to “den[y] to
women, simply because they are women, full citizenship stature—equal
opportunity to aspire, achieve, participate in and contribute to society based on
their individual talents and capacities.”
127
2. Sex Equality in Sport is a High-Value Social Good
Sport is one of the areas in which the sex equality project has particularly
thrived. The goals of competitive sport are “to showcase the best athletes, to
produce related goods for stakeholders, and to use sport as a means to spread
certain values throughout society. In all three respects, sport seek specifically to
reverse society’s traditional subordination of women by providing them with
opportunities for equal treatment and empowerment.”
128
The Olympic Movement supports sex equality in international sport by
setting aside separate competitive opportunities for males and for females. For
example:
FIFA sponsors a football (soccer) World Cup for men and a World Cup for
women so that both sexes have the chance to field teams, to experience high level
international competition, and to be regional and world champions in the sport.
Through the production of its various events, FIFA is able to promote the sport
and to express its emerging commitment to sex equality—or at least to the value
of showcasing empowered females.
129
FIFA President Gianni Infantino explained
the impact of the 2019 World Cup on the organization this way:
123. U.S. v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 533 (1996).
124. Id. at 533 (emphasis added).
125. Id. (distinguishing the “[s]upposed ‘inherent differences’” between the races and national
orgins and adding that “‘the two sexes are not fungible; a community made up exclusively of one [sex]
is different from a community composed of both’”). See also id. at 532 (“Without equating gender
classifications, for all purposes, to classifications based on race or national origin, the Court . . . has
carefully inspected official action that closes the door or denies opportunity to women (or to men).”).
126. Id. at 533 (emphasis added).
127. Id. at 516 (emphasis added).
128. Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 85.
129. FIFA Women’s World Cup France 2019 Watched by More Than 1 Billion, FIFA.
COM (Oct. 18, 2019),
https://www.fifa.com/womensworldcup/news/fifa-women-s-world-cup-2019tm-watched-by-moretha
n-1-billion [hereinafter FIFA Women’s World Cup France 2019]. See Andreas Themistokleous, The Need
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 103
More than a sporting event, the FIFA Women’s World Cup 2019 was a cultural
phenomenon attracting more media attention than ever before and providing a
platform for women’s football to flourish in the spotlight. The fact that we broke
the 1 billion target just shows the pulling power of the women’s game and the fact
that, if we promote and broadcast world-class football widely, whether it’s played
by men or women, the fans will always want to watch[.]
130
The official blog of the U.S. Department of State added that:
Every four years, the FIFA Women’s World Cup brings the participation and
empowerment of women through sports to the international stage and reminds us
of the essential contributions of women to societies around the world. From the
first tournament held in China twenty eight years ago to France today, the arena
of the Women’s World Cup not only continues to inspire, but also demonstrates
the progress that has been made through the leadership of female athletes, role
models and their supporters on gender equality. A key priority for the State
Department is to support women and girls’ empowerment across economic,
political, and social spheres. One of the ways we achieve this is through sports
diplomacy . . . as the U.S. Women’s National Team holds the Women’s World Cup
Champion title, the positive impacts of Title IX continue to be felt at home and
abroad.
131
Toward these same combined ends, the sport of athletics (track and field) has
men and women competing separately but at the same event in all of the same
disciplines and arenas.
132
From the international federation—formerly the IAAF
now World Athletics—pay is also equal. For example, a world record at the World
Championships is compensated at the rate of $100,000, whether it is set by a male
or a female.
133
At the 2019 World Championships, Dalilah Muhammad was the
for Female Role Models in Sport, MONEY SMART ATHLETE BLOG (Mar. 13, 2019), http://moneysmart
athlete.com/2019/03/13/the-need-for-female-role-models-in-sports/ (discussing research on the broader
effects of seeing strong female athletes and of the related Irish campaign, “If she can’t see it, she can’t
be it”).
130. FIFA Women’s World Cup France 2019, supra note 129.
131. Erin Brown, The 2019 FIFA Women’s World Cup: A Women’s Team That Dares To Shine, D
IPNOTE:
U.S. DEPT OF STATE OFFICIAL BLOG (July 8, 2019), https://blogs.state.gov/stories/2019/07/08/en/2019-
fifa-women-s-world-cup-women-s-team-dares-shine.
132. Eddie Pells & Pat Graham, Felix, Other Top Stars, Fight Track’s Pregnancy Penalty, A
SSOCIATED
PRESS (Sept. 28, 2019), https://www.apnews.com/80b9e2db9a614cef99fadc5f7f0f8902 (noting that some
sponsors have subjected female track and field athletes to a “pregnancy penalty”, but that exposure in
competition is equal because “Diamond League meets have just as many female events as male events”
and because “[t]he women’s side of the sport has long produced as much talent and star power as the
men”). See also Peter Bodo, Follow the Money: How the Pay Gap in Grand Slam Tennis Finally Closed,
ESPN.
COM (Sept. 6, 2018), https://www.espn.com/tennis/story/_/id/24599816/us-open-follow-money-
how-pay-gap-grand-slam-tennis-closed (noting that while pay is not equal across all tennis events, “the
equivalent prize money that men and women receive at Grand Slam events still puts tennis ahead of
other leagues and associations in terms of equality”).
133. See, e.g., Press Release, IAAF, TDK and QNB to Support World Record Program in Doha (Sept.
17, 2019), https://www.iaaf.org/news/press-release/world-championships-doha-2019-record-program
m. In 2019 in Doha, Dalilah Muhammad of Team USA and Team USA’s mixed 4x400m relay were
paid under this program, which has been the IAAF standard since the 2009. See IAAF $100,000 IAAF
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
104 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
only individual athlete to earn the bonus, for her world record in the women’s 400
meters hurdles;
134
and for her extraordinary achievements she was subsequently
celebrated, alongside Eliud Kipchoge, who broke the two-hour barrier in the
marathon, as the sport’s Athlete of the Year.
135
Sex equality in international sport remains an aspiration, not a perfected goal.
There is no doubt, however, that we have come a long way toward parity in this
setting even as it remains elusive in different institutional contexts. In important
part, this is because the sex affirmative measures in use in sport—including sex
segregation and a quota system which ensure an equal number of spots on teams,
in finals, and on podiums—have not been embraced elsewhere.
Females have most of the same matching opportunities domestically that
exist internationally, not only to participate but also to make those teams, finals,
and podiums; but here, as the State Department’s statement following Team USA’s
victory in the FIFA Women’s World Cup suggests, this is primarily the result of
Title IX’s equality mandate.
136
In the United States, most sport and athlete
development, and most competitions, take place under the auspices of secondary
and post-secondary educational institutions and affiliated sports organizations.
This includes state interscholastic athletic associations and the NCAA. These
institutions and organizations embrace sex equality not only because they have to
as recipients of federal funds and actors in interstate commerce, but also because
they understand the important social value that is created when opportunities for
participation and competition are distributed not only to boys and men but also to
women and girls. The set of synergistic goods that flow from sport to individual,
institutional, and community stakeholders is believed to be worth the investment.
Thus, starting in high school if not already in middle school, educational
institutions and affiliated organizations support separate local, state, regional, and
national competitions for males and females which are designed—like elite
sport—to isolate and celebrate the champions. They also support a combination of
co-ed and sex-segregated opportunities for participation, the latter as pathways to
developing competitive athletes and to inculcating the values of fitness and
athleticism for lifelong health and wellness. The opportunity to be engaged in
competitive sport in particular—regardless of the level at which the competition
occurs—is understood to impart additional socially valuable traits including
teamwork, sportsmanship, and leadership, as well as individually valuable traits
including goal setting, time management, perseverance, discipline, and grit.
137
World Record Programme Supported by TDK and Toyota – Berlin 2009, WORLD ATHLETICS (Aug. 12, 2009),
https://www.iaaf.org/news/news/100000-iaaf-world-record-programme-supported.
134. Scott Cacciola, Dalilah Muhammad Breaks Her Own World Record in the 400-Meter Hurdles, N.Y.
TIMES (Oct. 4, 2019), https://www.nytimes.com/2019/10/04/sports/dalilah-muhammad-world-record-
hurdles.html.
135. OlympicTalk, Dalilah Muhammad, Eliud Kipchoge Named World Athletes of the Year, NBC
SPORTS
(Nov. 23, 2019, 3:43 PM), https://olympics.nbcsports.com/2019/11/23/eliud-kipchoge-dalilah-muhamm
ad-world-athletics-athlete-year/.
136. See supra note 131 and accompanying text (quoting that statement).
137. Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 95–96.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 105
As in the international context, opportunities for participation and
competition are still not equal;
138
and compared to boys, girls have
“disproportionate drop-out rates . . . which [are] heightened as girls transition
from childhood to early adolescence.”
139
Nonetheless, because of Title IX and its
sports exception, it is no longer just boys and men who have the opportunity to
experience the sense of strength and power—both physical and mental—that
comes from consistent training and competition; the proverbial “thrill of victory”
and “agony of defeat”; the notion of failure as opportunity; and those “fourth and
goal” high intensity, high impact moments when the team is counting on the
individual to be at their best not only for themselves but also for the collective
endeavor. Because of Title IX and its sports exception, it is no longer just boys and
men who experience being celebrated as champions in their communities, who are
recruited to compete in college, and who provide the optics necessary for those
who look like them and come from their circumstances realistically to dream of
following in their footsteps. The latter point about optics is controversial in some
circles because it is focused on the female phenotype.
140
But as the pervasive
138. Congress continues to require institutions to produce an annual accounting of their efforts
toward Title IX’s equality mandate. See supra notes 64 and 68 and accompanying text (discussing the
Equity in Athletics Disclosure Act). And, litigation is ongoing to ensure that they are held accountable
also at the local level. See, e.g., Portz v. St. Cloud State Univ., No. CV 16-1115 (JRT/LIB), 2019 WL
6727122 (D. Minn. Dec. 11, 2019) (denying defendants’ motion to stay injunction requiring schools to
“take immediate steps to provide its female students with an equitable opportunity to participate in
varsity intercollegiate athletics and with an equitable athletic-related treatment and benefits at every
tier of its athletic department”; injunction was based on a finding that the schools “did not comply with
Title IX in its allocation of athletic participation opportunities and treatment and benefits and had not
since at least 2014); Robb v. Lock Haven Univ. of Pa., No. 4:17-CV-00964, 2019 WL 2005636 (M.D. Pa.
May 7, 2019) (denying summary judgment because facts are in dispute on the issue whether the
university’s plans to eliminate its women’s varsity swim team and demote its women’s varsity field
hockey team from Division I to Division II discriminated against female student athletes in violation of
Title IX’s requirement that schools provide “equivalently advanced competitive opportunities”); D.M.
by Bao Xiong v. Minn. State High Sch. League, 335 F. Supp. 3d 1136, 1139–40 (D. Minn. 2018), rev’d and
remanded, 917 F.3d 994 (8th Cir. 2019) (rejecting boy’s challenge to girls’-only competitive dance team
on the grounds that the exclusion is designed to delimit competitive opportunities for girls in state’s
high school sports space: “[I]t is not unfair discriminatory practice to restrict membership on an athletic
team to participants of one sex whose overall athletic opportunities have previously been limited”).
139. N
ICOLE ZARRETT, ET AL., WOMENS SPORTS FOUND., COACHING THROUGH A GENDER LENS:
MAXIMIZING GIRLS PLAY AND POTENTIAL, EXECUTIVE SUMMARY 1 (2019), http://www.womensspo
rtsfoundation.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/04/coaching-through-a-gender-lens-executive-summary-
web-1.pdf ; Laura Mallonee, The Importance of Photographing Women in Sports, W
IRED (June 26, 2019, 4:56
PM), https://www.wired.com/story/female-hockey-players-photo-gallery/ (“By age 14, girls drop out
of sports at a rate nearly twice that of boys, due to lack of access, social stigma, and other inequities.”).
140. See Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 91–93 (discussing the controversy over the optics
of the female body).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
106 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
mantra “If she can’t see it, she can’t be it” suggests,
141
it is both well-studied and
widely-embraced.
142
Finally, it is because of Title IX and its sports exception—together with the
fight that Title IX advocates have put to those who would impede the project—
that we have now experienced four generations of empowered little girls
becoming empowered women. According to Donna de Varona and Beth Brooke-
Marciniak, “Girls who play sport stay in school longer, suffer fewer health
problems, enter the labor force at higher rates, and are more likely to land better
jobs. They are also more likely to lead. [Ernst & Young] research shows stunningly
that 94% percent of women C-Suite executives today played sport, and over half
played at a university level.”
143
Although we have not been able to verify their
particular numbers,
144
and education-based sport is certainly not the only path to
141. See, e.g., Themistokleous, supra note 129 (discussing the use of this phrase by the Federation
of Irish Sport); Melody Glenn, If She Can’t See It, She Can’t Be It: Part 1, F
EMINEM (May 25, 2017),
https://feminem.org/2017/05/25/cant-see-cant-part-1/ (using this phrase in support of female role
models in emergency medicine). The phrase is a variant of others such as “you can’t be what you can’t
see” that have also been applied to the cause of women’s equality and the use of female role models in
that context. See, e.g., Tasnuva Bindi, If You Can’t See It, You Can’t Be It: Female Founders Crushing
Stereotypes, S
TARTUP DAILY (May 13, 2014), https://www.startupdaily.net/2014/05/cant-see-cant/ (using
this phrase in support of female role models in business, tech, and politics).
142. It is beyond legitimate dispute that role models are effective when their observable
characteristics and trajectories are relevant to the aspirant. This is why, for example, we say that girls
need to see women in positions of authority and that children of color need to see people of color in
those same positions. What we can see—the optics—matter. And the point of reference is the viewer
or aspirant, not the individual who would self-identify as a role model. See Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra
note 27, at n.256; Z
ARRETT, ET AL., supra note 139, at 3 (listing “female coaches” as one of the things that
can encourage girls to stay engaged in sport once they have chosen to participate: “Girls more readily
identify with and see a female coach as a mentor and role model, which in turn, can help counter
stereotypes and boost girls’ confidence, self-efficacy, and sense of belonging.”). See also Coleman,
Semenya and ASA v. IAAF, supra note 49 (“It is well understood that the empowerment effects of [sex
segregated female sport] are different from those that result from seeing men compete together, and
also different from seeing open competition among men and women.”).
143. Beth A. Brooke-Marciniak & Donna de Varona, Amazing Things Happen When You Give Female
Athletes the Same Funding as Men, W
ORLD ECON. FORUM (Aug. 25, 2016), https://www.weforum.org/
agenda/2016/08/sustaining-the-olympic-legacy-women-sports-and-public-policy/.
144. See also Rebecca Hinds, The 1 Trait 94 Percent of C-Suite Women Share (And How to Get It), I
NC.
MAG. (Feb. 8, 2018), https://www.inc.com/rebecca-hinds/the-1-trait-94-percent-of-c-suite-women-sha
re-and-how-to-get-it.html (citing these EY statistics and noting that being “former or current athletes”
is “a trait that Meg Whitman, Indra Noovi, Marissa Mayer, and many other top female executives
possess”); Monica Miller, 4 Female C-Suite Executives Who Played College Sports, NCAA
AFTER THE GAME
(Mar. 8, 2018), http://www.ncaa.org/student-athletes/former-student-athlete/4-female-c-suite-executiv
es-who-played-college-sports (noting that being a former athlete is a characteristic top female
executives share); Valentina Zarya, What Do 65% of the Most Powerful Women Have in Common? Sports,
F
ORTUNE (Sept. 22, 2017), https://fortune.com/2017/09/22/powerful-women-business-sports/ (same).
We were especially interested in the study design that resulted in the 94 percent figure and so sought
to establish how the company that ran the survey—Longitude—identified its recipients. A
representative from the company explained that “[a]t the time of recruiting for a particular study, our
vendors reach out to the general survey audience and screen respondents according to the survey
requirements. Due to the nature of our work, we therefore deploy purposive sampling methods where
we purposely target a specific type of audience to eventually qualify the right people.” E-mail from
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 107
the C-Suite,
145
its multiple health, welfare, competence, and confidence effects have
been well-understood for decades.
146
Indeed, as the award-winning sports reporter
Christine Brennan offered in the wake of Team USA’s victory at the 2019 FIFA
Women’s World Cup:
This is a watershed moment. The 1999 U.S. Women’s World Cup victory was a
revelation. Back then, the nation fell in love with what it created with Title IX. But
this, the 2019 U.S. Women’s World Cup victory—this is an affirmation. This is the
nation saying, ‘We want to see more of this.’ We’ve been watching these little girls
running to practice every day in our neighborhoods for a couple of decades. They
grow up and this is what happens. They become strong, powerful, fearless women
who can do anything. The success of the 2019 U.S. soccer team is set against the
backdrop of more than 100 women in Congress and 25 women in the Senate. This
is that conversation, #MeToo, women speaking out, equal pay, it’s all wrapped in
one.
147
The women on this and other teams stand on the shoulders of their predecessors
and all of them started in school.
148
3. Sex Segregation is Necessary to Protect This Good
If schools could not “carve out an exclusive [girls’ and] women’s category
defined by sex, females and their associates would be excluded from the most
important of the[] benefits” that flow from participation in competitive sport.
149
As we explain in Part II, this is because females as a group are not competitive
with males as a group beginning from the onset of male puberty. Starting then,
Ali Syed, Research Operations Manager, Longitude to Eugene Volokh, Gary T. Shchwartz,
Distinguished Professor of Law, UCLA Law Sch. (May 20, 2019, 8:40 AM) (on file with authors). We
were not provided with further detail about how the company’s purposive approach may have
influenced who received and responded to the survey. The approach may have caused the number to
be higher than it would have been otherwise.
145. Sport is one way that individuals can gain the set of traits that are commonly associated with
success. It is ultimately that set of traits that is valuable to employers. See, e.g., Christina DesMarais, 7
Reasons Athletes Make the Best Employees, I
NC. MAG. (Nov. 22, 2017), https://www.inc.com/christina-
desmarais/heres-why-kids-who-play-sports-do-better-in-life.html?cid=search (describing the traits are
commonly associated with athleticism); Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 96 (noting that the traits
athletes develop “are socially valuable in part because they are highly transferrable . . . which is why
‘executives like to hire athletes’”); Nanette Fondas, Research: More Than Half of Top Female Execs Were
College Athletes, H
ARV. BUS. REV. (Oct. 9, 2014), https://hbr.org/2014/10/research-more-than-half-of-fem
ale-execs-were-college-athletes (same).
146. See Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 95–96; Donna Lopiano, Modern History of Women in
Sports: Twenty-five Years of Title IX, 19 C
LIN. SPORTS MED. 163, 163–73 (2000).
147. E-mail from Christine Brennan, Sports Columnist, CNN, to Doriane Lambelet Coleman,
Professor of Law, Duke Law Sch. (Aug. 17, 2019, 10:14 AM) (on file with authors) (discussing CNN
broadcast on day of Team USAs return from France to the parade in New York City).
148. Women’s Interest in Sport Continues to Grow, I
BERDROLA, https://www.iberdrola.com/about-us/
womens-sport/other-sports/women-sport-today (last visited Jan. 28, 2020) (detailing “the influence of
participation in sports at school [beginning in the 1970s] on women’s sustained interest in sports now”).
149. Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 96.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
108 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
even the very best females are surpassed by second-tier males, and second-tier
females have no realistic chance to be anything but early participants in the game.
The case for re-affirming the sports exception is based in the goods produced
by girls’ and women’s sport and in the causal link between sex segregation and
those goods. The more specific case for not including—or for conditioning the
inclusion of—transgender women and girls in girls’ and women’s sport is related:
If they haven’t been on feminizing hormones for a relevant period of time,
150
trans
women and girls remain fully male-bodied in the respects that matter for sport;
because of this, their inclusion effectively de-segregates the teams and events they
join.
151
Beyond this basic structural point is the fact that if they are just decent
athletes, they will displace females who are the classification’s raison d’être,
152
including in championship positions.
153
This matters for the individual females
who are displaced, for those who would aspire to be champions, and for the
broader expressive effects we expect from the classification. Even an exception
risks swallowing the rule and defeating the category.
Finally, the position that there is no legally cognizable difference between
females and trans women and girls destroys the legal basis for separate sex
sport.
154
This position—encapsulated in the movement mantra, “Girls who are
transgender are girls. Period.”
155
—is presumably designed to erase sex-linked
traits from consideration in the analysis whether the two groups are similarly
situated for purposes of equal protection doctrine. If we are not permitted legally
to notice that girls who are female and girls who are transgender are dissimilarly
situated with respect to their anatomy and physiology, and if we are not permitted
to distinguish among them in circumstances where sex actually matters, we will
have dismantled the legal scaffolding that supports separate sex sport. Unlike
restrooms, which are segregated for safety and privacy, sport does not have an
argument that it needs to separate girls from boys, men from women, for any
reason other than sex.
156
And, sex discrimination, including sex segregation, is only
lawful if it is necessary.
150. Feminizing Hormone Therapy, MAYO CLINIC, https://www.mayoclinic.org/tests-procedures/ mt
f-hormone-therapy/about/pac-20385096 (last visited Jan. 28, 2020).
151. See supra notes 91–102 and accompanying text (summarizing the effects of male puberty on
the body).
152. See supra notes 81–88 and accompanying text (explaining that even second-tier males routinely
surpass not only second-tier females but also the very best elite females). We don’t separate men from
women, girls from boys, in competitive sport because they have a different gender identity; we separate
them because they have different sex-linked anatomy and physiology. See supra and infra notes 111–
114 and 218 and accompanying text (elaborating on this point).
153. See infra notes 181–182 and accompanying text (noting recent victories by trans women
athletes on and not on hormones).
154. See supra notes 77–78 and accompanying text (describing this legal point).
155. See, e.g., Support Trans Student Athletes, ACLU, https://action.aclu.org/petition/support-trans-
student-athletes?ms_aff=NAT&initms_aff=NAT&ms=190726_lgbtrights_transathletepledge&initms=1
90726_lgbtrights_transathletepledge&ms_chan=tw&initms_chan=tw&redirect=transathletesbelong
(last visited Jan. 28, 2020).
156. For additional analysis of the difference between sport and restrooms, see supra notes 72–74
and accompanying text.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 109
B. The Affirmative Case for Inclusion on the Basis of Gender Identity
There are important arguments on the other side. From our perspective, this
is the most persuasive case:
A just and ethical society aspires to be inclusive of and to secure equal
protection for all of its citizens, especially for its most vulnerable. Because schools
are one of the settings in which children learn societal values, a just and ethical
society inculcates inclusivity through its educational programming, and then
ensures that all students have equal access to high value spaces and opportunities.
Education-based sports are among the high value spaces and opportunities
schools provide. Eligibility rules for teams and events that sort students based on
biological sex may have the effect of excluding those who are transgender. (This
effect exists when individual transgender students are sufficiently uncomfortable
with the barrier to entry that they choose to exclude themselves.) When this
happens, they are denied equal access to sports. It also denies their schools and
athletic associations the ability to pursue their pedagogical goals and to perfect
themselves as just and ethical institutions. Finally, where a particular student is
especially vulnerable, schools and organizations acting in quasi loco parentis are
denied the means to secure their health and welfare.
1. Equality and Inclusivity as Hallmarks of a Just and Ethical Society
A just and ethical society aspires to be inclusive of and to secure equal
protection for its most vulnerable citizens. Policies that exclude or deny them
equal access are flawed as a matter of principle because they have these effects,
and because they impede the perfection of a virtuous society. Where the policies
are otherwise valuable, a just and ethical society should provide for exceptions.
Where their value is in doubt and cannot be established, they should be
dismantled. The goal should be to acknowledge everyone’s humanity, to practice
generosity, and to make room at the table for everyone. It is often difficult but
especially important to do so in the face of incomprehensible or inexperienced
difference.
In the international context, “social integration to create an inclusive society
… [is] one of the key goals of social development.”
157
For example, the United
Nations Department of Economic and Social Affairs understands social
integration to be “a dynamic and principled process of promoting the values,
relations and institutions that enable all people to participate in social, economic,
cultural, and political life on the basis of equality of rights, equity and dignity.”
158
Social inclusion “is understood as a process by which efforts are made to ensure
equal opportunities for all, regardless of their background, so that they can achieve
their full potential in life.”
159
157. UNITED NATIONS DEPT OF ECON. & SOC. AFFAIRS, CREATING AN INCLUSIVE SOCIETY:
PRACTICAL STRATEGIES TO PROMOTE SOCIAL INTEGRATION 4 (2009) (draft), https://www.un.org/esa/soc
dev/egms/docs/2009/Ghana/inclusive-society.pdf.
158. Id. at 3.
159. Id.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
110 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
In the domestic context, these same inclusion and equal access goals
motivated the creation of the Civil Rights Division of the Department of Justice in
1957, the passage of the 1964 Civil Rights Act, and, among other subsequent civil
rights legislation, the Americans with Disabilities Act. Throughout, the idea has
been to re-define “We the people” in our Constitution to include all of us within
its protections. And then, through the law and the social movements that
constantly re-work its application, to evolve the culture and social norms also to
be inclusive of and even generous toward those who were previously excluded.
As we do, we not only make room at the table but we also perfect our society.
In both the international and domestic contexts, civil and human rights
advocates have called on states and institutions to make room at the table for trans
people specifically, by protecting them from discrimination and securing their full
social integration according to these principles. This advocacy
[s]eeks to persuade institutional decisionmakers to develop policies designed to
recognize, normalize, include, and empower . . . trans people who throughout
history have been erased or severely marginalized and often subject to violence . .
. [T]he trans community . . . is . . . particularly “associated with high levels of
stigmatization, discrimination and victimization, contributing to negative self-
image and increased rates of other mental disorder.” For example, in the United
States, “[t]ransgender individuals are at a higher risk of victimization and hate
crimes than the general public” and “[a]dolescents and adults with gender
dysphoria are at increased risk for suicide.” In less tolerant parts of the world,
trans people are at even greater risk of violence, social isolation, and reduced life
span.
160
We are in the midst of this particular social movement, which has garnered
important support. In the United States, the 116th Congress passed H.R. 5 - The
Equality Act in 2019, which re-defines “sex” in federal civil rights law to include
“gender identity.”
161
This move was designed to make it unlawful to discriminate
against individuals based on their gender identity; among other things, it would
disallow distinctions among people on the basis of sex. Because it faces significant
opposition in the Republican-controlled Senate and President Trump likely would
not sign it, it probably will not become law; but the vote in the House of
Representative expresses an important social and political viewpoint. Also in 2019,
a consortium of the most important human rights organizations within the United
Nations signed a joint statement “call[ing] on States [and other stakeholders] to act
urgently to end [among other things] . . . discrimination against . . . transgender
and intersex . . . adults, adolescents and children.”
162
Like H.R. 5, this statement is
160. Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 102. For example, in the United States, the Human
Rights Campaign “envisions a world where LGBTQ people are ensured of their basic rights, and can
be open, honest and safe at home, at work and in the community.” HRC’s Mission Statement, H
UMAN
RIGHTS CAMPAIGN, https://www.hrc.org/hrc-story/mission-statement (last visited Jan. 28, 2020). Its
Transgender Equality Council advocates specifically for full inclusion and equality for “transgender
children and gender expansive youth.” Explore: Transgender Children & Youth, H
UMAN RIGHTS
CAMPAIGN, https://www.hrc.org/explore/topic/transgender-children-youth (last visited Jan. 28, 2020).
161. Equality Act, H.R. 5, 116th Cong. (2019).
162. Ending Violence and Discrimination Against Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual, Transgender and Intersex
People, U
NITED NATIONS (Sept. 2015), https://www.ohchr.org/Document/Issues/Discrimination/
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 111
not itself formal law, but it nevertheless demonstrates important support for the
cause.
2. The Mission of Schools in a Just and Ethical Society Includes Providing
Equal Access and Inculcating and Expressing Inclusivity
Part of the mission of educational institutions in any society is to inculcate
and express community values. The extent to which they do depends on whether
the institutions are public or private, and also on the degree of consensus within
the community about what those values are. Where there is ideological
homogeneity, values are most likely to be inculcated through the schools. Where
there is ideological heterogeneity, this is less likely.
In a just and ethical society, there is or should be a high degree of consensus
that inclusivity and equality are among the most important societal values.
Educational institutions within such a society are likely to be permitted or even
required by the government and citizenry to inculcate and express both. Doing
this successfully means ensuring that school programming is accessible to all
students. This is especially important with respect to high value spaces and
opportunities which are most likely to be arbitrarily exclusive if they are not
carefully monitored.
Education-based sport, including competitive sport, is understood to be a
high value space and opportunity. This is because of the direct physical and health
benefits it yields, and because in elementary and secondary school sports are
also—if not mostly—a co-curricular social space where students learn to interact
successfully with their peers. Because of this, all students should have access to
school sports and related structures should be designed to make this possible.
It is noteworthy that school sports programming has traditionally provided
the basis for inculcating inclusivity. While this is especially evident in the context
of noncompetitive games, it is also apparent in lower level competitive ones.
“Everyone can play” policies, rotation and substitution practices, and the selection
of teams balanced by ability are all ways in which the existing practices of
competitive education-based sport express and inculcate inclusivity.
Providing equality of opportunity for transgender students is consistent with
this approach and the values that drive it. Because they may be excluded in effect
by programming that sorts students according to their sex, it is arguably
incumbent on schools and athletic organizations either to sort students differently
or to accommodate them within existing structures according to their gender
identity. Like other students, transgender students should have the benefit of the
positive social, health, and empowerment effects of school sports. Rashaan
Joint_LGBTI_Statement_ENG.PDF (adopted by the International Labour Organization, Office of the
High Commissioner of the United Nations Human Rights Council, UNDP, UNESCO, UNFPA,
UNHCR, UNICEF, UNODC, UN Women, World Food Programme, World Health Organization, and
UNAIDS); see also U
NITED NATIONS, THE ROLE OF THE UNITED NATIONS IN COMBATTING
DISCRIMINATION AND VIOLENCE AGAINST LESBIAN, GAY, BISEXUAL, TRANSGENDER AND INTERSEX
PEOPLE: A PROGRAMMATIC OVERVIEW (2019), https://www.ohchr.org/Documents/Issues/Discrimin
ation/LGBT/UN_LGBTI_summary_2019.pdf.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
112 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
Yearwood, an educator who is also the father of a transgender girl, expresses the
point this way:
My daughter is a trans-female. That means she needs to compete on girls’ teams
in order to feel most comfortable. [This isn’t about competition for her.] She’s
running because she wants to be part of a team at this age. You know, comradery.
Perseverance, grit, teamwork. My job is to raise a healthy child. And we all know
that being part of groups and being included allows students to develop in a
healthier way than when you’re excluded.”
163
Because all students gain from exposure to important social values, including
transgender children in school activities like sport according to their gender
identity separately supports the institutions’ broader pedagogical goals.
3. Schools Need to be Able to Take Care of the Especially Vulnerable Child
Schools stand in quasi loco parentis. Although they are not formally in the
shoes of parents, they do have physical custody of the children during the school
day while they are on campus, and their charge is not only to ensure that the
children are safe but also that they are prepared to engage and to learn. Where an
individual child is especially vulnerable—where they might not be safe or when
the environment is such that they might be unable successfully to participate—
schools should have the tools to address their circumstances.
This is a commonplace. When a child has a peanut allergy, we say that other
children cannot bring peanut butter to school. When a child becomes ill, it is or
should be “all hands on deck.” The interests of the at-risk child are understood to
outweigh the interests of others in their teachers’ focused attention or in their
lunch preferences or even their nutritional needs. This balancing analysis does not
always come out in the vulnerable child’s favor—for example when they are
disruptive of the educational process, when they risk the health and welfare of
other children, or when the school is not and cannot be equipped to handle their
special needs. But it should come out in their favor when the interests on the other
side are not so significant.
Not all transgender children are struggling and fragile. Being trans does not
mean having dysphoria.
164
But many are and do. Individual transgender students
may be struggling and fragile because of the discordance between their sex and
their gender identity, because they are in the process of transitioning socially and
maybe also physically, and because of the ways in which others perceive and treat
them:
The disconnect between their experienced gender and their assigned gender can
result in acute stress called gender dysphoria. Gender dysphoria can be a source
of profound suffering. A recent study of transgender teens found that more than
50 percent of transgender males and almost 30 percent of transgender females
reported attempting suicide. Transgender adolescents are often vulnerable to
163. Nia Hamm, Father of Transgender Student Athlete Pushes Back Against Petition to Change
Competition Policy, F
OX 61 (June 26, 2018), https://fox61.com/2018/06/26/father-of-transgender-student-
athlete-pushes-back-against-petition-to-change-competition-policy/.
164. See Safer & Tangpricha, supra note 31, at 2451 (explaining this point).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 113
bullying and family rejection. And even when families are supportive, it can be a
very difficult transition for both the teen and the parents.
165
The medical standard of care for trans and gender diverse children includes living
and having others treat them in accordance with their gender identity.
166
Although
medicine can’t prescribe other-than-medical policy, schools should take that
standard under advisement as they develop their policies; and they should follow
it in individual instances when the benefits of doing so outweigh the costs. As
applied, taking care of transgender children means including them in sex
segregated spaces and opportunities like sport on the basis of their gender
identity. Where the individual child is especially vulnerable, supporting their
successful social transition is arguably more important than the integrity of the
sex-segregated competitions they would enter. If the student is a transgender girl,
supporting her is arguably more important than the interests of all female students
in winning.
This last argument is often coupled with evidence that transgender teens are
at an especially high risk of suicide. For example, Helen Carroll of the National
Center for Lesbian Rights explains that “[s]port can be life-saver for transgender
people, who are at high risk of suicide . . . ‘They’ve been fighting themselves and
feeling like they’re in the wrong body, and sport gives them a place to be happy
about their body and what it can do.’”
167
Carroll is right on the facts; an
extraordinarily disturbing 30 to 50 percent of transgender teens report attempting
suicide.
168
Carroll herself continues to be invaluable to all stakeholders in her
support for trans athletes within existing structures.
169
But of course her point is
165. Caroline Miller, Transgender Kids and Gender Dysphoria, CHILD MIND INST.,
https://childmind.org/article/transgender-teens-gender-dysphoria/ (last visited Jan. 28, 2020). See also
Doriane Lambelet Coleman, Transgender Children, Puberty Blockers, and the Law: Solutions to the Problem
of Dissenting Parents, 19 A
M. J. BIOETHICS 82 (2019) (addressing the question whether and how the law
is able to assist transgender children whose families are not supportive).
166. News Release, Endocrine Soc’y, Endocrine Society Urges Policymakers to Follow Science on
Transgender Health (Oct. 29, 2019), https://www.eurekalert.org/pub_releases/2019-10/tes-esu102919.
php (“As noted in our evidence-based guideline, transgender individuals, both children and adults,
should be encouraged to experience living in the new gender role and assess whether this improves
their quality of life.”). See also Jason Rafferty, Ensuring Comprehensive Care and Support for Transgender
and Gender-Diverse Children and Adolescents, 142 P
EDIATRICS 1 (2018); https://pediatrics.aappublications.
org/content/pediatrics/142/4/e20182162.full.pdf (American Academy of Pediatrics does the same.);
Joshua Safer & Vin Tangpricha, Care of the Transgender Patient, A
NNALS OF INTERNAL MED. (July 2, 2019),
https://annals.org/aim/article-abstract/2737401/care-transgender-patient (American College of
Physicians guidelines support the same.).
167. Christie Aschwanden, Trans Athletes Are Posting Victories and Shaking Up Sports, W
IRED (Oct.
29, 2019, 12:00 PM), https://www.wired.com/story/the-glorious-victories-of-trans-athletes-are-shaking-
up-sports/.
168. Rokia Hassanein, New Study Reveals Shocking Rates of Attempted Suicide Among Trans
Adolescents, H
UMAN RIGHTS CAMPAIGN BLOG (Sept. 12, 2018), https://www.hrc.org/blog/new-study-rev
eals-shocking-rates-of-attempted-suicide-among-trans-adolescen.
169. See generally Cyd Zeigler, LGBTQ Sports Advocate Helen Carroll Retires From NCLR, O
UTSPORTS
(June 1, 2017, 10:27 PM), https://www.outsports.com/2017/6/1/15723406/helen-carroll-nclr-lgbtq-spo
rts-retire and infra note 225 and accompanying text (discussing her work with Pat Griffin on the NCAA
transgender guidelines).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
114 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
an application of more general ones, about the empowerment effects of sport for
females and its therapeutic effects for those who are suffering as a result of difficult
personal and mental health issues whatever their source.
170
It is an unfortunate
fact that major depression and associated feelings of hopelessness are on the rise
among children in the United States, with girls being especially affected.
171
Suicide
is now the second leading cause of death among adolescents in general.
172
Risk
factors include “psychiatric disorders and comorbidities, family history of
depression or suicide, loss of a parent to death or divorce, physical and/or sexual
abuse, lack of a support network, feelings of social isolation, and bullying
173
as
well as “barriers to access treatment, homosexual orientation” and being an “early
or late developing girl[].”
174
Educational institutions that have the necessary
resources should follow the evidence and do what they can to mitigate these risks
regardless of the child at issue.
175
There is a related, overlapping claim from vulnerability. It is that as a group,
transgender children are struggling and fragile so that their interests in being
included in sex-segregated spaces and opportunities on the basis of their gender
identity always trump the interests of classmates who, as a group, cannot be
described as similarly vulnerable. This is a standard move in advocacy circles
which has, in turn, influenced sports policymakers on the ground. For example,
the Executive Director of the National Federation of State High School
Associations Karissa Niehoff argues that:
[This] is not about the winning and losing. It’s about the successful development
of these [transgender] kids. [I]f we don’t treat them respectfully, their
development is going to lose. That’s a much bigger issue than someone not getting
a medal or a place in a race. Much bigger issue.
176
170. See generally Emily Pluhar et al., Team Sport Athletes May Be Less Likely To Suffer Anxiety and
Depression Than Individual Sport Athletes, 18 J.
SPORTS, SCI., & MED. 490 (2019) (noting positive mental
health effects of sports in general while distinguishing results in team and individual sports); Nick
Pearce et al., The Role of Physical Activity and Sport in Mental Health, F
ACULTY OF SPORT & EXERCISE MED.
UK (May 2018), https://www.fsem.ac.uk/position_statement/the-role-of-physical-activity-and-sport-
in-mental-health/.
171. Patti Neighmond, A Rise In Depression Among Teens and Young Adults Could Be Linked to Social
Media Use, NPR (Mar. 14, 2019, 11:01 AM), https://www.npr.org/sections/health-shots/2019/03/14/703
170892/a-rise-in-depression-among-teens-and-young-adults-could-be-linked-to-social-medi.
172. Melonie Heron, Deaths: Leading Causes for 2017, 68 N
ATL VITAL STAT. REP. 1 (2019).
173. Teen Suicide, A
MERICAS HEALTH RANKINGS, https://ww.americashealthrankings.org/explore/
health-of-women-andchildren/measure/teen_suicide/ state/ALL (last visited Jan. 28. 2020).
174. Stephanie Secord Fredrick et al., Can Social Support Buffer the Association Between Depression and
Suicidal Ideation in Adolescent Boys and Girls?, 55 P
SYCHOL. IN THE SCHOOLS 490, 491 (2018).
175. See generally C
TRS. FOR DISEASE CONTROL & PREVENTION, NATL CTR. FOR INJURY PREVENTION
& CONTROL, DIV. OF VIOLENCE PREVENTION, THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN BULLYING AND SUICIDE:
WHAT WE KNOW AND WHAT IT MEANS FOR SCHOOLS (2014), https://www.cdc.gov/violenceprevention/
pdf/bullying-suicide-translation-final-a.pdf.
176. Mary Albl, CIAC’s Transgender Policy Faces Test With New Lawsuit, D
YESTAT (June 24, 2019,
1:20 PM), https://www.runnerspace.com/gprofile.php?mgroup_id=44531&do=news&news_id=58023
8.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 115
Niehoff’s statement reflects the sense that the successful development of different
kids is not similarly dependent on equality, inclusion, and success in school and
sport; and that to the extent it might be, this will either be an only occasional
conflict, or else the opportunity to participate will be enough for most or all kids
who are not transgender. It also reflects the view that although education-based
sport sometimes promotes competition and winning, this is ultimately not its
primary institutional focus.
* * *
We close out this section with brief reactions to four arguments that are not
persuasive from our perspective. They include some that are particularly
prominent in the public relations strategies of the advocacy groups that currently
control the megaphone.
The first of these is the argument, grounded in science denial, that we have
already addressed in Part II.
177
It is fact, not myth or stereotype, that beginning at
the onset of male puberty, an insurmountable performance gap between males
and females emerges such that even the very best females are not competitive for
the win against males, including against second-tier males. If we care about sex
equality in sport, that is, if we care about seeing females in finals and on the
podium however they might happen to identify, competitive sport has to be
segregated on the basis of sex.
The second is the suggestion that because there are few transgender women
and girls relative to the numbers of females, any disruption of the competitive
hierarchy is unlikely to be substantial enough to jeopardize sex equality goals.
178
That some transgender women and girls may be on feminizing hormones is said
to reduce their potential impact even further. As we explain in Part III(C) below,
we agree that a consistent course of hormone replacement therapy (HRT) can wind
down the male advantage to the point that a policy exception at the development
elite and collegiate levels is justified. But we don’t think that transition hormones
should be a requirement for participation in secondary school competition; and in
any event, many transgender teens do not want or have access to hormones. As
students in the latter category are increasingly comfortable coming out at school—
which from our perspective is a good thing—the number of “out” trans kids is
growing beyond the small percentages described in earlier population surveys.
This increase is not yet well understood, but it appears to be an upward
trajectory.
179
Because it is well-established that athletic but not necessarily elite
177. See supra Part II. See, e.g., Medley & Sherwin, supra note 72 (describing as “myth” and
“impermissible sex stereotype” the fact of the sex-linked performance gap, and as “arbitrary” the rules
of sports governing bodies that use sex-linked traits as the basis for classification into and out of the
women’s category, and claiming that there is “ample evidence that girls can compete and win against
boys”).
178. See, e.g., id. (“The truth is, transgender women and girls have been competing in sports at all
levels for years, and there is no research supporting that they maintain a competitive advantage.”).
179. See Rafferty, supra note 166 (discussing recent statistics); Michelle M. Johns et al., Transgender
Identity and Experiences of Violence Victimization, Substance Use, Suicide Risk, and Sexual Risk Behaviors
Among High School Students—19 States and Large Urban School Districts, 2017, 68 CDC
MORBIDITY &
MORTALITY WKLY. REP. 67 (reporting a 1.8 percent incidence rate as of 2017); Jesse Singal, When Children
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
116 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
males dominate females in almost every sport and event, which is true without
regard to how individuals identify, it is reasonable to expect that trans girls not on
hormones will affect results in important ways—as athletes with 46,XY differences
of sex development have in the international arena.
180
It is not a fluke that, in the
last three years, we have seen the first trans girls as state champions,
181
the first
trans woman as DII national champion,
182
and the first potentially consequential
trans woman in a DI sport.
183
The third is the political and sociological claim
184
that transgender girls are
girls and, because of this, their reproductive sex-linked traits are irrelevant to the
conversation about their classification into spaces and opportunities designed
specifically to empower females.
185
This claim is weak not only because it has its
Say They’re Trans, ATLANTIC (July/Aug. 2018), https://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2018/07
/when-a-child-says-shes-trans/561749/ (reporting on rise in numbers of people identifying as trans).
180. See Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 106–108 (responding to the numbers argument in
that context).
181. See 2018 CIAC Spring Championships: Class M Outdoor Track, supra note 104 and accompanying
text (discussing Connecticut state championships in track and field).
182. Press Release, Franklin Pierce Univ., NATIONAL CHAMPION! Telfer Claims Women’s Track
& Field’s First NCAA Title (May 26, 2019), https://www.franklinpierce.edu/about/news/Nation
al_Champion_CeCe_Telfer.htm.
183. Kyle Hansen, Montana Cross Country Runner, Belgrade Native to Make History as Transgender
Athlete, M
ISSOULIAN (Aug. 30, 2019), https://missoulian.com/sports/college/big-sky-conference /univers
ity-of-montana/montana-cross-country-runner-belgrade-native-to-make-history-as/article_2a 37bd80-
9eea-519d-8636-040473b84cc8.html. As of this writing, June Eastwood’s performances appear to be
consistent with Joanna Harper’s hypothesis that, at least for distance runners, a year of consistent use
of gender affirming hormones winds down the male advantage to the point that trans women return
to their place in the hierarchy, e.g., roughly speaking if they were the tenth best man they will be
approximately the tenth best woman. Eastwood’s announcement that she was transitioning from male
to female, and from the Montana men’s team to the Montana women’s team, sounded alarm bells
within the sport, however, because her pre-transition times in high school and early college, especially
in the middle distances, would have immediately put her at or close to the professional women’s world
records. In this respect she was, and depending on how she runs going forward may still be, the most
significant trans woman athlete to date.
184. We characterize this as a political and sociological claim because it is based in an effort to
expand the standard definitions of female, girl, and woman beyond their basis in female reproductive
sex to include a subset of individuals whose reproductive sex is male. It is one of a number of strategies
that might be employed to secure equality for trans people. There is a counterargument that this is a
factual claim since gender identity likely has a neurobiological basis and may be related to our natural
reproductive inclinations. Even if this is eventually established, however, individuals would still have
either male or female reproductive sex, which is what the words and dichotomies male/female,
girl/boy, and man/woman are generally understood to connote; and we would still need words that
did this descriptive work. The arguments that we wouldn’t or shouldn’t, or that it shouldn’t or couldn’t
be the ones we use now because they exclude trans people, are undoubtedly political.
185. See, e.g., Medley & Sherwin, supra note 72 (rejecting the “policing of gender [that] has been
used to justify subjecting transgender student athletes to numerous additional barriers to participating
in sports, from onerous medical requirements to segregation in locker rooms to outright bans on their
participation”); Statement of Women’s Rights and Gender Justice Organizations, supra note 29 (rejecting any
distinctions among cis and trans women and girls on the argument that “Transgender girls are girls
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 117
advocates making easily dismissed arguments about testes and T levels being no
different than—for example—height and wingspan, but also because it ignores the
reasons these spaces and opportunities exist and censors legitimate discussions
about the implications of erasing biological sex even where it is undoubtedly
relevant. This includes contexts in which sex is outcome determinative, like
competitive sport. It also includes contexts in which sex differences are an
affirmative individual and societal good. Discussions about sex and sex-linked
anatomy and physiology must be had kindly, but it is wrong to censor them.
186
The fourth is the argument from intersectional feminism that it is good for all
women that we accept that transgender women are women, and that transgender
girls are girls.
187
Accepting trans women and girls is the good and right thing to
do for a lot of reasons, including that our default should be inclusion unless there
are persuasive reasons to make distinctions. But the suggestion that women
should understand that eliding relevant sex differences is good for them
particularly—even if they don’t know it—is patronizing and otherwise deeply
problematic.
188
From what we have gathered, it appears to be based in a number
of different assumptions all of which we reject: that sex classifications are always
and transgender women are women. They are not and should not be referred to as boys or men,
biological or otherwise”).
186. For an analysis of the harm caused by the censorship of females talking about the female body
see Doriane Lambelet Coleman, A Victory for Female Athletes Everywhere, Q
UILLETTE (May 3, 2019),
https://quillette.com/2019/05/03/a-victory-for-female-athletes-everywhere/.
187. See, e.g, Statement of Women’s Rights and Gender Justice Organizations, supra note 29 (“[W]e . . .
reject the suggestion that cisgender women and girls benefit from the exclusion of women and girls
who happen to be transgender”; “we recognize the harm to all women and girls that will flow from
allowing some women and girls to be denied opportunities to participate and cast out of the category
of ‘woman’ for failing to meet standards driven by stereotypes and fear”; “we speak from experience
and expertise when we say that nondiscrimination protections for transgender people—including
women and girls who are transgender—are not at odds with women’s equality or well-being, but
advance them.); Support Trans Student Athletes, supra note 155 (“The marginalization of trans student-
athletes is rooted in the same kind of gender discrimination and stereotyping that has held back
cisgender women athletes. Transgender girls are often told that they are not girls (and conversely
transgender boys are told they are not really boys) based on inaccurate stereotypes about biology,
athleticism, and gender. . . . Girls who are transgender are girls. Period.”). See also, e.g., Carol Hay, Who
Counts as a Woman, N.Y.
TIMES (Apr. 1, 2019), https://www.nytimes.com/2019/04/01/opinion/trans-wom
en-feminism.html (noting the origins of this claim in intersectional feminism); Jack Guy, Women or
‘Womxn’? Students Adopt Inclusive Language, CNN (Nov. 27, 2018, 11:38 AM), https://www.cnn.com/20
18/11/27/uk/womxn-inclusive-language-gbr-scli-intl/index.html (describing the “growing use of
inclusive language, designed to avoid excluding particular groups of people” including that “Womxn
is a more inclusive term which promotes intersectionality” and is thus “more inclusive of all kinds of
women, including trans women” and that “Womxn is used to demonstrate our commitment to
inclusiveness”).
188. Especially patronizing is the suggestion that these organizations have particular “experience
and expertise” about women—including about how they should define themselves and their
wellbeing—that women themselves don’t have. See, e.g., Statement of Women’s Rights and Gender Justice
Organizations, supra note 29 (“[W]e speak from experience and expertise when we say that
nondiscrimination protections for transgender people—including women and girls who are
transgender—are not at odds with women’s equality or well-being, but advance them.”). It is this kind
of talk that has alienated many, including many women, who might otherwise be natural allies.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
118 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
harmful or at least a net harm to women and girls; that all sex classifications are
based in false and damaging sex stereotypes; that women all want or should want
to be freed from the yoke that is their secondary sex characteristics and cultural
expectations around femininity; that women and girls are by nature or necessity
inclusive and self-sacrificing, so that the category that describes them itself should
be generously so; and that women and girls—and their allies—don’t or shouldn’t
care as much as boys and men do about competition and being competitive for the
win. We reject each of these because they are themselves false and damaging sex
stereotypes.
The last of these is especially problematic as we discuss the future of Title IX.
It has led a group of prominent civil rights organizations to return to the posture
of some of their 1970s counterparts who argued that high-end NCAA-style
competitions were not for women;
189
today, they have determined to limit their
advocacy to protecting opportunities for women and girls to participate—not
necessarily to win—in sport.
190
It is presumably just helpful coincidence and not
coordinated strategy that their position aligns with the position of some in the
trans advocacy community that because trans women and girls are women and
girls, their victories in events in which females retain opportunities to participate
should be celebrated, not discredited.
191
This move is particularly insidious as
applied to the high school sports space which can be described as relatively
unimportant to protect if it’s really just about participation.
189. See supra notes 42 and 48 and accompanying text (describing that earlier position); and
Interview with our co-author Donna Lopiano, President & Founder, Sports Mgmt. Res. (Oct. 13, 2019),
(noting that in the development of Title IX, “the focus on participation opportunities came first,
followed by the focus on competition, because we had to build the ranks of those participating before
we could think about competition, but also because early advocates preferred a health-focused,
student-led, physical education model that would concentrate on intramural or junior varsity style
events, as distinguished from the varsity and NCAA commercial model for competition they rejected”).
190. Id. (noting that women’s organizations that fought for both participation and competition
opportunities in earlier periods have decided as a strategic matter to focus their efforts going forward
on participation numbers and not to use organizational resources to continue to secure and protect the
right of women and girls also to win, i.e., also to spots in finals and on podiums); E-mail from N.F. to
M.R. (Mar. 23, 2019, 3:17 PM) (on file with authors) (sharing that “the Title IX advocacy community is
in lockstep” in its commitment to the unconditional inclusion of trans kids in high school sports on the
basis of their gender identity so that the right of cis-girls to more than just participation in this—as
opposed to the college sports—space “is not the battle of [the organizations] at this time”). This
position appears to be reflected in the approach of the Connecticut CIAC, among other state athletic
associations. See New Hampshire House Bill 1251, S
AVE WOMENS SPORTS (Jan. 15, 2020), https://savewom
enssports.com/original-articles/f/new-hampshire-house-bill-1251-hearing (quoting a testimonial from
Connecticut mother, Christy Mitchell, “I was astounded to hear from state officials that ‘girls have the
right to participate not to win.’”).
191. See, e.g., Rachel McKinnon, I Won a World Championship. Some People Aren’t Happy., N.Y.
TIMES
(Dec. 5, 2019), https://www.nytimes.com/2019/12/05/opinion/i-won-a-world-championship-some-peo
ple-arent-happy.html (“Trans women are women. We are female . . . It is a human right to be able to
compete. I will continue to show up. I hope you’ll consider cheering.”); Dave Zirin, Transphobia’s New
Target Is The World of Sports, supra note 72 (“Terry Miller and Andraya Yearwood finished first and
second place respectively in the state open indoor-track championships last month. Instead of
celebrating one of the great moments in their lives, they were immediately put on the defensive about
their right to compete in the first place.”).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 119
The proposition that females don’t need to be competitive for the win is no
longer viable; see the FIFA Women’s World Cup.
192
The proposition that
showcasing strong female-bodied champions is not a high value social good is no
longer viable; see Serena Williams and Allyson Felix.
193
We do not doubt that they
are well-intentioned, but coming in 2020, from organizations that otherwise decry
sex stereotypes and that previously championed the right of women and girls also
to equality of competitive opportunity, they are nothing short of extraordinary.
We need to take care of transgender women and girls, but the path should not
involve weakening the commitment to females. And here we should be clear: It
is weakening the commitment to females and to sex equality to accept that the
boys’ state championship will probably always be won by a male where the girls’
state championship will not always be won by a female.
C. Updating Title IX for Its Next Half Century
Biological sex matters. It is real, not socially constructed; and it affects
peoples’ lives, opportunities, and experiences in even the most benign or
egalitarian situations and societies. In particular, because of their different
reproductive biology and secondary sex characteristics, females in general have
different physical capacities and experiences than males. This is true regardless of
how they identify.
Sex matters in ways that are empowering and celebrated, and also in ways
that are damaging and censured. For females, physical—including sexual—
violence perpetrated primarily by males is a destructive commonplace, as are the
routine exclusions and subordinations they experience based on their phenotype
and their reproductive biology. Sometimes these exclusions and subordinations
are driven by false stereotypes. But they may also be driven by a reluctance to re-
imagine structures to accommodate real and otherwise appreciated sex-linked
physical differences. Regardless, sex is relevant if not defining.
Sex equality also matters. Although we can imagine a world in which sex is
not relevant or defining, in which we classify people on entirely different terms or
else not at all, this isn’t ours. As ours exists, because sex matters, so does sex
equality. The United Nations is not wrong to think about the world’s population
in male and female halves, because this is how we tend in the first instance to sort
ourselves, and then how our experiences and opportunities line up. They
generally line up this way, again at least in the first instance, without regard to
race, class, or gender identity. Because of this, it is also not wrong to make anti-
subordination commitments specifically to the female half of the world’s
population. This should not be our only anti-subordination commitment, but is it
an entirely rational and important one.
192. See also ZARRETT, ET AL., supra note 139, at 3 (noting that one of the things that can work to
encourage girls to stay engaged in sport once they have chosen to participate is “[a]n emphasis on
winning . . . when combined with an emphasis on fun and skill development . . . . Healthy forms of
competition are ideal for fostering girls’ engagement”).
193. Mallonee, supra note 139 (“One of the biggest things researchers are finding that keeps girls
engaged in sports is access to their heroes and mentors—even if it’s just seeing them . . . [t]o see a
banner or a poster or an ad featuring someone like you is monumental.”).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
120 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
Sex equality can sometimes be achieved without affirmative consideration of
sex, and in this period in the United States, sex-blind policies are preferred. But
when sex blindness would be counterproductive, ineffective, or insufficiently
remedial, sex conscious approaches should be tools in the equality toolbox. These
are especially useful in circumstances where, to fix inequities, it is important to
see, not to erase, the female body. This includes at least aspects of the workplace;
the military; medicine and bio-medical research; and competitive sport. If we were
to have to ignore sex differences in these circumstances, sex equality would remain
elusive.
Efforts to secure inclusion and equality for transgender people that are
premised on erasing sex and sex differences—conceptually and from the
discourse—are fundamentally incompatible with these facts, priorities, and
approaches. Where sex, including being able to name it, is central for many if not
most females, both are anathema for many in the transgender community. For
this reason, but also because it fits their legal and political strategy, some trans
rights advocates seek to redefine sex to be or to include gender identity; and
further to ensure that no distinctions can be made on the basis of sex on the ground
that such distinctions are a rejection of transgender people.
194
Those who do not
play ball are labeled “transphobic” and, if they are liberal and feminist, also as
“trans exclusionary radical feminists” (TERFs), which is intended as an insult.
195
The competitive sports question is hard, maybe even impossible to resolve
with a win on all sides, because what females need to have recognized is precisely
what advocates for trans students suggest should be erased. For example, if we
continue to be committed to equality for females in relation to males in the high
school sports space—equality not only for its own sake but also for the myriad
individual, institutional, and societal benefits that flow from its terms—we need
structures that recognize sex differences in athletic performance and that sort
athletes on the basis of sex.
196
At the same time, because they are properly focused
on the individual children in their care—and not on the implications for others of
their approach—erasure of these same sex differences has been built into the
therapeutic model developed by pediatricians working with transgender children,
and impressed on their educational custodians.
197
As we have already discussed, efforts to will this collision away do not work
because they rest on a series of ultimately unacceptable fictions: That all sex is
socially constructed stereotype that inures to the detriment of women. That there
are no cognizable differences between women who are transgender and women
who are not. And that “women” is a concept that, in its best iteration, describes
194. See supra notes 29–30 and accompanying text.
195. Colleen Flaherty, ‘TERF’ War, I
NSIDE HIGHER ED (Aug. 29, 2018), https://www.insidehigher
ed.com/news/2018/08/29/philosophers-object-journals-publication-terf-reference-some-feminists-it-re
ally. See R (on the Application of Miller) v. College of Policing & Chief Constable of Humberside, [2020]
EWHC 225 (Admin) [225], ¶ 241–46 (Eng.) (describing and quoting the expert witness statement of
Professor Kathleen Stock on the use of the term ‘TERF’ in the context of the gender-related divisions
among feminist academics).
196. See supra notes 112–114, 149–156 and accompanying text.
197. See supra note 166 and accompanying text.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 121
people who are relatively anti-competitive and selfless and so do not mind being
relegated to the bench if this is necessary to secure the health and welfare of others
who may be more vulnerable.
198
The competitive sports question is also hard because it involves claims for
inclusion and equality from both sides; and, because of how sport and sex-linked
biology work together, including one group necessarily means excluding or
limiting the opportunities of the other. The carve-out that is the sports exception
to Title IX’s general, sex-blind nondiscrimination rule recognizes this. And so, to
secure the inclusion of and equality for females, it formally permits—but also
sometimes requires—schools to exclude males from their sports and events.
199
Carving out what would be, in effect, an exception to this exception for the subset
of males who identify as women and girls would result in their inclusion; but it
would have exclusive effects in the other direction. Longer term, it would
inevitably signal that we don’t actually need sex segregation, which would result
in the full re-integration of sport and thus the re-exclusion of females. Shorter term,
because competition itself is exclusionary in the sense that making teams requires
try-outs and cuts, and making it through to the finals and championships involves
a version of the same—there can be only one state, regional, or national
champion—carving out an exception to the sex segregation rule for males who
identify as women and girls will result in the exclusion of females from teams,
finals, and podiums.
200
The problem is hard but, in general, there are four possible approaches:
affirming the carve-out as a biological classification tied to natal sex; re-imagining
the carve-out as an identity classification; re-imagining the carve-out as a
biological classification tied to the onset of male puberty; and formalizing an
accommodations approach.
1. Affirming the Carve-Out as a Biological Classification Tied to Natal Sex
The first option is to affirm the traditional approach. This approach ties
eligibility to natal sex, which would generally be based on the sex recorded at birth
on the individual’s birth certificate. It is mostly efficient and effective because
natal sex and sex recorded at birth are typically the same, and both typically
correspond to the relevant primary and secondary sex characteristics that matter
for sport.
Nevertheless, the traditional approach is both over and underinclusive: On
the one hand, it includes trans boys and trans men who go on puberty blockers
and gender affirming hormones beginning at the onset of female puberty; as a
result, these athletes develop the male secondary sex traits that girls’ and women’s
sport exist to exclude. On the other hand, it excludes trans girls and trans women
who do the same at the onset of male puberty, and who, as a result, never develop
those traits.
198. See supra notes 185–193 and accompanying text.
199. See supra notes 52–53 and accompanying text.
200. See supra notes 104–105 and accompanying text (detailing how this has already happened in
the State of Connecticut and how the related data are being used in a Title IX OCR complaint).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
122 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
In addition, many jurisdictions now permit people who are transgender to
change the sex that is recorded on their birth certificates so that it accords with
their gender identity; in some places, parents can do the same for their children.
201
Depending on the jurisdiction, the individual need not have gone on hormones
before making this switch; that is, the switch may be permitted on some form of
self-declaration.
202
As a result, at least for some trans people, the sex recorded on
the birth certificate is no longer a reliable proxy either for natal sex or for the
relevant sex traits.
Because of these administrative and policy concerns, but also because the law
requires sex-related criteria to be closely tailored to institutional ends, we do not
support this approach. In our view, transgender women and girls should not be
excluded from girls’ and women’s sport if they have not gone through any part of
male puberty. Moreover, to include transgender men and boys who are on gender
affirming androgens is, in effect, no different from condoning the use of
performance enhancing drugs. Still, whether it is as a matter of choice or inertia,
many jurisdictions continue to provide that natal sex as recorded on the
individual’s birth certificate is the standard for eligibility for sex segregated sport.
203
2. Re-imagining the Carve-out as an Identity Classification
The second option is to abandon the carve-out for females only. This would
necessarily entail a rejection of the legitimacy and value of the claim from females
for equality in relation to males in the education-based competitive sports space.
It would involve either the full integration of sports and events, that is, all would
be co-ed; or it would involve a challenge to re-imagine girls’ and women’s sport
as a category that includes anyone who identifies as a girl or woman most broadly
defined, even if they retain their full male-linked performance advantages. The
best analog would be to an all-women’s college that admits and retains students
who identify as women regardless of their sex.
204
Advocates for transgender rights have persuaded many secondary school
athletic associations to adopt this approach. The unfounded claim that it is
required by Title IX may have been at play in some cases.
205
Nevertheless, it is
201. See generally ID Documents Center, NATL CTR. FOR TRANSGENDER EQUAL., https://transequality.
org/documents (last updated Jan. 2020) (providing state-by-state information and details on New York
City rules permitting parents to change their child’s birth certificate).
202. See id.
203. See High School Policies,
TRANSATHLETE, https://www.transathlete.com/k-12 (last visited Jan.
28, 2020).
204. See, e.g., Jeremy Bauer-Wolf, At Women’s Colleges, Rules Vary Widely for Trans and Nonbinary
Students, E
DUC. DIVE (Nov. 18, 2019), https://www.educationdive.com/news/at-womens-colleges-tra
ns-and-nonbinary-applicants-face-inconsistent-rules/567537/; Rebecca Brenner Graham, Women’s
Colleges Should Admit Trans Students. It’s Wholly Consistent with Their Mission, W
ASH. POST (Jan. 10, 2019),
https://www.washingtonpost.com/outlook/2019/01/10/womens-colleges-should-admit-trans-women-
its-wholly-consistent-with-their-mission/.
205. See supra notes 70–76 and accompanying text (discussing the state of the law); supra note 203
(providing an up-to-date description of state high school athletic association policies). See e.g.,
Complaint Targets Transgender HS Track Athletes, ESPN (June 20, 2019), https://www.espn.com/high-sch
ool/story/_/id/27015115/complaint-targets-transgender-hs-track-athletes (discussing the claim that
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 123
viable in the long run only if these advocates can convince law and policy makers
at the national level that Title IX should be revised to these ends. Specifically, they
will need to convince the federal government that the original Title IX carve-out
for females in sport is not a commitment it wants to keep; but that we still need—
and need to support with federal funds—two classifications, both of which would
be comprised of a combination of males and females, and both of which would see
males in championship positions.
These are important hurdles, particularly in an adverse political climate. Not
only have the last two administrations held firm to the premise that distinctions
on the basis of sex in Title IX sport are necessary and appropriate, but also, this
policy choice appears to be based in or at least consistent with a clear, bipartisan,
nationwide consensus in favor of the traditional approach.
206
Nevertheless, the
option is attractive to those who prefer that education-based sport focus on
opportunities for participation not competition, including whenever possible in
co-ed settings.
207
It is also attractive to those whose focus is specifically on the
health and welfare of transgender people, rather than on females, on the view that
at least in this period, the former need support more than the latter.
208
Finally, it is
attractive to those who prefer a wait-and-see to a precautionary approach to
restrictions on eligibility; they predict that trans women and girls won’t have an
important impact on girls’ and women’s sport, but that we can re-evaluate if they
do.
The best argument in favor of this approach today is based in the view that
almost everyone has a gender identity that aligns with their natal sex, in the still
small numbers of trans girls and women who seek to be classified according to
their gender identity, and in the fact that, until recently, we had not known of any
in championship positions. Until recently, including them was—in effect—a non-
category defeating accommodation within the existing sex segregated structure.
As Rachel McKinnon has argued,
Title IX requires the inclusion of trans girls in girls sport); Reference Guide for Transgender Policy, CONN.
INTERSCHOLASTIC ATHLETIC CONF., https://www.casciac.org/pdfs/Principal_Transgender_Discussion
_Quick_Reference_Guide.pdf (last visited on Feb. 19, 2020) (explaining that “[t]he CIAC has concluded
that it would be fundamentally unjust and contrary to applicable state and federal law to preclude a
student from participation on a gender specific sports team that is consistent with the public gender
identity of that student for all other purposes”).
206. See supra notes 69–76 and accompanying text. See, e.g., Most Oppose Transgender Athletes on
Opposite Sex Teams, R
ASMUSSEN REP. (June 4, 2019), https://www.rasmussenreports.com/public _conten
t/lifestyle/social_issues/most_oppose_transgender_athletes_on_opposite_sex_teams (finding that “just
28% of American Adults favor allowing transgender students to participate on the sports team of the
gender they identify with”). Given that this is a breakout conversation, see supra note 69, this number
is likely to shift in one or the other direction, as is the number representing undecideds, i.e., 18 percent
in the same survey.
207. See infra note 208 and accompanying text (describing this position).
208. See Navratilova, Coleman & Richards-Ross, supra note 89 (noting that “Advocates of the
Equality Act who know sports or aren’t science deniers . . . [argue] that it’s time to shift our focus from
supporting female-bodied athletes for whom Title IX has already done a lot of work, to supporting
transgender women and girls who [now] need our help more”).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
124 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
Since the 2004 Athens Olympics, there have been over 54,000 Olympians. Not one
of them has been openly trans. There also aren’t any cases of men pretending to
be (trans) women. Next year, there are a few athletes who have the potential to be
the first openly trans athlete to compete in the Games. None are a medal favorite.
This is not the beginning of the end of women’s sports.
209
This moment is passing quickly, however, as more children identify as
transgender; as we are learning to embrace them as they are; as they are
increasingly comfortable coming out in high school even if they are not on
hormones; and as advocacy to establish trans rights is increasingly successful in
other contexts.
210
This includes recent legislation in the United States and in many
countries around the world that permits trans people more easily to reform their
identity documents to provide that their legal sex is their gender identity.
211
As
we have already noted, it is not a coincidence that it is in the last three years we
have seen the first male-to-female transgender state, national, and international
champions in girls’ and women’s Olympic events,
212
and that international
regulators are working to ensure that policies are in place to address the expected
increase in numbers.
213
McKinnon herself made history when she won gold in the women’s sprint
event at the 2018 and 2019 Masters Track Cycling World Championships and in
the process set a women’s world record.
214
She is a trans woman who has met the
hormonal conditions required for inclusion in women’s cycling events; she is
playing by the rules established by her governing body.
215
Those rules are in play,
however. On the one hand, many have expressed concern that they insufficiently
account for the legacy advantages retained by trans women who physically
transition after puberty.
216
On the other, some, including McKinnon, have argued
that they should be revised to permit unconditional inclusion on the view that
trans women are women based on their gender identity, without respect to the
decisions they might take privately about gender affirming hormones or
209. McKinnon, supra note 191.
210. See supra note 179.
211. See, e.g., ID Documents Center, supra note 201 (providing up-to-date information on relevant
state laws and practices).
212. See supra notes 181–182 and 209 and accompanying text.
213. Press Release, World Athletics, International Federations Discuss Consensus on Establishing
Rules for Transgender Athletes (Oct. 31, 2019), https://www.worldathletics.org/news/press-release/inte
rnational-federations-rules-transgender-a.
214. Karleigh Webb, Trans Cyclist Rachel McKinnon Keeps Winning Championships and Her Detractors
Don’t Like It, O
UTSPORTS (Oct. 23, 2019), https://www.outsports.com/2019/10/23/20928252/rachel-mckin
non-trump-cycling-trans-athletes-transphobia-world-championships.
215. McKinnon, supra note 191.
216. See, e.g., Sean Ingle, Sports Stars Weigh in on Row Over Transgender Athletes, G
UARDIAN (Mar. 3,
2019), https://www.theguardian.com/society/2019/mar/03/sports-stars-weigh-in-on-row-over-transge
nder-athletes (summarizing this argument). For a good description and evaluation of the debate
around legacy advantages, see generally Ross Tucker, On Transgender Athletes and Performance
Advantages, S
CI. SPORT (Mar. 24, 2019), https://sportsscientists.com/2019/03/on-transgender-athletes-an
d-performance-advantages/?doing_wp_cron=1576790435.8559970855712890625000.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 125
surgery.
217
Although the call for unconditional inclusion has not yet succeeded in
the elite sport space, related efforts directed at state high school athletic
associations across the United States have altered that landscape.
3. Re-Imagining the Carve-Out as a Biological Classification Tied to Puberty
In 2019, in the challenge brought by Caster Semenya to the eligibility criteria
for the women’s category in the sport of track and field, the Court of Arbitration
for Sport (CAS) explained that:
the purpose of the male-female divide in competitive athletics is not to protect
athletes with a female legal sex from having to compete against athletes with a
male legal sex. Nor is it to protect athletes with a female gender identity from
having to compete with athletes with a male gender identity. Rather, it is to protect
individuals whose bodies have developed in a certain way following puberty from
having to compete against individuals who, by virtue of their bodies having
developed in a different way following puberty, possess certain physical traits that
create such a significant performance advantage that fair competition between the
two groups is not possible.
218
Consistent with this rationale, the third approach affirms the carve-out for those
who have not experienced male puberty. We peg this to male puberty to include
in the classification all those who cannot be said to have developed the male sex-
linked advantages that justify sex-segregated sport. It would include all females—
however they identify—so long as they are not on masculinizing hormones; and
all trans girls who, because they were on blockers and then feminizing hormones,
have not experienced male puberty. This option is a challenge to imagine
education-based sport as analogous to the medical setting, where sex and
associated physical characteristics remain relevant; and where gender identity and
expression are for the individual to resolve and others to respect as they would
any central aspect of an individual’s personhood.
This option is attractive for several reasons:
It is fully consistent with the carve-out’s raison d’être and with its legal
grounding.
219
In the language of the law, an approach that hews closely to this
rationale is, as required, narrowly tailored and neither over- nor under-inclusive.
Moreover, as in other modern contexts where physical facts remain relevant
to the enterprise, it distinguishes only on those objective grounds and otherwise
respects the inherently personal nature of gender identity and expression. That is,
it does not seek to establish, judge, or sort anyone on those different grounds
that—in contrast with the physical—are ultimately unrelated to the institution’s
goals. But it does commit to respecting them without challenge. As it should be
217. See, e.g., Charlie Ashworth, Women’s Sports: Rachel McKinnon Believes Trans Women Have a
‘Human Right’ to Compete, G
IVE ME SPORT (Oct. 21, 2019), https://www.givemesport.com/1514948wome
ns-sports-rachel-mckinnon-believes-trans-women-have-a-human-right-t-ocompete (“By preventing
trans women from competing or requiring them to take medication, you’re denying their human
rights.”).
218. Mokgadi Caster Semenya & Athletics S. Afr. v. Int’l Ass’n of Athletics Fed’ns, CAS
2018/O/5794 ¶ 559 (2019).
219. Id.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
126 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
developmentally, there is no questioning by a school or athletic association of a
child’s credibility about or commitment to a particular gender identity or
expression; nor is there a requirement that they agree to be fixed for a season or an
academic year to their expressed preferences. They can be who they are, including
in flux, throughout the relevant period.
Consistent with Title IX’s original design, all females who are not on
transition hormones—however they might identify—have a space in which they
can not only play but also compete for the win. Except in the rare case of an
exceptionally precocious child star, the policy cannot be said to incentivize a
student’s choice to go on gender affirming hormones. And because they have
benefitted from either endogenous or exogenous male testosterone levels, the
subset of trans kids who start on hormones only after the onset of puberty is not
be eligible to compete in the female category; but they are eligible to participate
and welcome in the male category, and—importantly—their private needs and
choices will not dictate outcomes for others. In this respect, this option is the least
disruptive of the existing model that does a lot of good work for the vast majority
of stakeholders.
It would be most easily implemented in circumstances where school sports
teams don’t have to train separately, that is, where only competition itself needs
to be sex segregated. In such contexts, the social aspects of participation in
education-based sport would not be linked to sex or gender. Swimming, cross
country, and track and field are among the sports where—at least as practiced in
some places—a version of this model already exists.
220
The principal costs associated with this approach are as follows:
Because it is not simply a re-naming of the existing sex-segregated structure,
imagining the classifications as we suggest would take work, even if everyone
were on board. This work would range from the relatively simple and technical to
the more difficult and conceptual. For example, we would have to decide what to
call the classifications and how to establish where students belong. We have
labeled the classifications “male” and “female” here, but they could be labeled
differently. Uniform rules would need to be changed to allow students to select
the style that makes them most comfortable regardless of sex or gender. And the
notion of school sports as sex or gender-specific social spaces would need to be
wound down. The latter would be resisted by traditionalists but also by some
trans kids and their advocates who embrace binary sex classifications and see
inclusion within them as having the potential to contribute to their successful
transition.
221
Finally, regardless of how respectful and welcoming the environment is
made for gender diverse students within the categories, those who may be passing
do not want to be outed by sex classifications. Others who are not passing but who
suffer from dysphoria and are deeply (not just politically) hurt by references to
their sex-linked traits may continue to be effectively excluded from participation
220. See, e.g., Josh Weinreb, Thetford Academy Transgender Runner Embraces Her Identity and Gains
Freedom, VALLEY NEWS (May 25, 2019, 9:25 AM), https://www.vnews.com/Running-career-has-helped-
Thetford-Academy-senior-Bel-Spelman-navigate-her-gender-identity-24764677.
221. See supra note 166 and accompanying text (noting this strategy).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 127
and competition. Still others who do not suffer from dysphoria but who prefer to
occupy spaces where sex is irrelevant may reject school sport because it is still so
focused. To the extent the institution could and should produce important health
and welfare benefits for these individuals, this approach would not be effective.
As is the case today for kids who for various reasons eschew school sports, some
will remain left out or will choose to exclude themselves.
4. Formalizing an Accommodations Approach
The fourth option is to affirm the commitment to the Title IX carve-out for
females but also formally to grant authority to policymakers to accommodate
gender diverse students in ways that are not category defeating. Accommodations
are often preferred in circumstances that involve competing rights claims.
222
To
date, some form of this approach has been preferred by those working most
thoughtfully on inclusion in the elite sports space, for example within the Olympic
Movement, the NCAA, and the National Scholastic Athletics Foundation
(NSAF).
223
Although it has not been formally tested to date, the NCAA policy is
especially relevant as it operates within institutions governed by Title IX. It
permits transgender student-athletes to compete either according to their natal sex
or their gender identity. In the latter case, if the athlete is a trans man, they are
required to have a therapeutic use exemption (TUE) if they are on gender affirming
hormones (testosterone); and if they are a trans woman, they are required to have
been on testosterone suppressants for at least a year before they are eligible for
women’s teams and competitions.
224
We do not have enough studied experience
with trans women and girls in sport to know that suppression to a certain level for
a given period of time is sufficient to wind down male-linked advantages to the
point where they are not category defeating in particular sports and events.
Nevertheless, the rule fits the model because it presumes an ongoing primary
commitment to female athletes, which is the raison d’être for the sports exception
to Title IX’s non-discrimination rule; and it includes trans women when they meet
222. See, e.g., Notice, Enforcement Guidance: Reasonable Accommodation and Undue Hardship Under the
Americans with Disabilities Act, U.S. Equal Emp. Opportunity Comm’n (Oct. 17, 2002), https://www.
eeoc.gov/policy/docs/accommodation.html (applying the model in the context of conflicts between
employers and employees with disabilities). Accommodation is related to compromise. See, e.g., Dale
Eilerman, Agree to Disagree: The Use of Compromise in Conflict Management, M
EDIATE (Oct. 2006),
https://www.mediate.com/articles/eilermanD7.cfm (describing when compromise is useful in
mediation).
223. Almost all elite sports institutions have adopted a rule of conditional inclusion based on
testosterone levels. See, e.g., IOC Consensus Meeting on Sex Reassignment and Hyperandrogenism, I
NTL
OLYMPIC COMM. (2015), https://stillmed.olympic.org/Documents/Commissions_PDFfiles/Medical _co
mmission/201511_ioc_consensus_meeting_on_sex_reassignment_and_hyperandrogenism-en.pdf;
NCAA Inclusion of Transgender Student-Athletes, N
ATL COLLEGIATE ATHLETIC ASSN (2011), https://132
48aea-16f8-fc0a-cf26-a9339dd2a3f0.filesusr.com/ugd/2bc3fc_4a135824fabc462183c71357c93a99b4.
pdf; National Scholastic Athletic Foundation Transgender Participation Policy and Procedure, N
ATL
SCHOLASTIC ATHLETICS FOUND. (2019), https://www.nationalscholastic.org/nbin/transgender/.
224. NCAA Inclusion of Transgender Student-Athletes, supra note 223, at 13.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
128 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
relevant physical conditions.
225
At least conceptually, because testosterone is the
primarily driver of the performance gap, the accommodation is viable as category
affirming not defeating. As an evidentiary matter, and thus legally, the rule would
be especially defensible if the NCAA were to establish a maximum allowable T
level that is within the female range and then to develop a protocol for monitoring
compliance.
226
A different example of the accommodations approach outside of elite sports
can be found in the policies of state athletic associations that have experience
integrating male students who are not transgender into girls’ sports and events.
This happens where there is no boys’ team and the male students can show—
consistent with Title IX requirements—that they are the excluded sex. Where
particular males threaten to disrupt the championship experience and hierarchy,
officials have sought solutions to their inclusion that are consistent with the goals
of the carve-out, such as adding lanes or running separate male and female
sections of a final, and featuring separate podiums for male and female finishers.
Consistent with the goals of the sports exception to Title IX’s general non-
discrimination rule, this has ensured that male student-athletes are not precluded
from participating in their chosen sports, but also that there cannot be a male
winner of the girls state championship.
227
These strategies aren’t perfect fits, given
that trans girls and women identify as girls and women, not as boys and men. But
since sport is segregated on the basis of sex, not identity, and identity is ultimately
irrelevant to sports performance, they can be useful as examples of solutions that
might resolve certain impasses.
Other models that could be adapted depending on the sport and event are
quotas and adjusted scores and start lines. Quotas might be especially useful in
team sports situations. Joanna Harper and Tiffany Abreu have suggested they
could work in volleyball and basketball, for example.
228
The basic concept of
adjusted scores and start lines comes from golf, which designate different Tee
boxes for males and females and—to level the playing field for golfers of different
abilities—use adjusted scores (handicaps) to compare relative performances.
225. According to the Justice Department, the NCAA rule was developed in “consult[ation] with
medical experts, athletics officials, affected students, and [with advocates for transgender student-
athletes].” Dear Colleague Letter, supra note 73 (citing NCAA Inclusion of Transgender Student-
Athletes 2, 30–31, and Pat Griffin & Helen J. Carroll, On the Team: Equal Opportunity for Transgender
Student Athletes (2010)). On the Team itself notes that “policies that may be appropriate at the college
level may be unfair and too complicated for [the high school] level of competition.” It thus encourages
the development at the high school level of age-appropriate policies. Id. at 26. It was co-authored by
two of the leading players in this area, Helen Carroll of the National Center for Lesbian Rights (NCLR)
and Pat Griffin of the University of Massachusetts Amherst, in consultation with Shannon Minter, also
of the NCLR, and Eric Vilain, who also consulted on the IOC policy. Both Minter and Vilain are leading
experts in their respective fields, i.e., civil rights litigation and biological sex, respectively.
226. As of this writing, although we expect that most trans girls and women on hormones follow
the medical standard of care which has a target of well under 5 nmol/L, the NCAA has not set a
maximum allowable level, nor does it monitor compliance.
227. See, e.g., Coleman, Sex in Sport, supra note 27, at 173–77 (describing the State of Massachusetts’
approach to the inclusion of boys in girls’ swimming events).
228. Darlington, supra note 116.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 129
Different start lines could be adjusted based on the sport’s average performance
gap between males and females, in the manner that the distance between Tee
boxes is adjusted to reflect the relative power of female and male golfers, and
scores could be adjusted at the outset on the same group—rather than individual—
basis. More complicated iterations of golf’s handicapping system have been
described elsewhere.
229
Ultimately, the key to such approaches would be assuring
their efficacy and their administrative feasibility.
Like accommodations in general, accommodations in sport have the benefit
of being adaptable over time based on new knowledge. For example, as we learn
more about the nature and extent of the legacy advantages of going through male
puberty, as well as about their particular effects in different sports and events, the
specific requirements within the model could be adjusted without altering the
commitment to the model itself. And as we develop a better sense of the political
community’s relative commitments to female sport on the one hand and to trans
inclusion on the other, the reasonableness of specific conditions within models will
also evolve.
The merits of and problems inherent in accommodations models are that they
tend mostly, but not entirely, to satisfy principal policy goals while reducing, but
not eliminating, the concerns of affected individuals. In other words, like all
compromises, accommodations generally mean that no one gets everything they
wanted; and, depending on the specifics, one or the other side still faces a complete
loss. As it considers the question of transgender inclusion, sport is no different.
Purists on both sides of the debate decry all proposed concessions: Those who
want girls’ and women’s sport to remain exclusively for females say they cannot
abide a solution that would ever see a transgender athlete in a championship
position, even if she is following all of the rules. Those who want girls and
women’s sport to be unconditionally inclusive of transgender athletes say they
cannot abide a solution that recognizes that there is a difference between females
and transgender women and girls: “Transgender women are women. Period.
Transgender girls are girls. Period.” Those who argue from “the messy middle”
can struggle to get a foothold. But given the stakes on both sides, it is surely
worthwhile also to consider solutions in this space.
D. Our Recommendations
Because sex equality in education-based sport produces enormous value,
and because the development of inclusive policies is separately consistent with
educational institutions’ goals, policymakers should affirm Title IX’s original
design and work to include gender diverse students within that design. Because
institutional goals are different in non-elite and elite settings, approaches to
inclusion should track those different goals. Throughout, policymakers should
endeavor to develop strategies that will encourage as many students as possible
to remain engaged in school sports as participants and as competitors.
Where it can be effective to all ends to combine teams or at least team
practices and only to segregate competition itself on the basis of sex, the approach
229. See, e.g., Aschwanden, supra note 167 (discussing the concept in general and the work of Alison
Heather and colleagues in particular).
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
130 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
we detail in Part IIIC3—re-imagining the carve-out as a biological classification
pegged to pubertyshould be preferred. So long as it doesnt result in diminished
coaching opportunities for females who remain underrepresented in those ranks
or deter female students from staying engaged with sport, it is the most inclusive,
least intrusive, and simplest to administer. Existing co-ed arrangements can be an
ongoing model for this purpose.
Where combined teams or practices coupled with sex segregated competition
cannot accomplish institutional goals, the accommodations approach detailed in
Part IIIC4 should be adopted. This will be the case in circumstances where sex
segregated teams and events remain necessary to secure parity of opportunity for
females. Where the accommodations approach is adopted, trans students will train
and compete consistent with their gender identity so long as their inclusion can be
relevantly conditioned. The NCAA transgender policy is illustrative of a hormonal
condition in this category; others that do not require medicalization— such as
handicaps, offsets, and quotas—exist as more appropriate models for the high
school sports space.
In high school intramural, junior varsity, and regular season play, where
institutional goals are primarily related to health and fitness and to the
development of social skills, unconditional inclusion of gender diverse students
according to their gender identity rather than their sex will usually be category
affirming. Exceptions will arise where this is not the case, for example in contact
sports situations where physical safety is tied to sex-linked differences, and where
regular season play determines invitational and post-season opportunities. But to
the extent that including trans students according to their gender identity merely
makes others uncomfortable, educators should be encouraged to educate,
including to inculcate empathy and inclusivity, rather than to exclude.
Once the focus shifts to competition and to the establishment of hierarchy and
the isolation and celebration of champions, unconditional inclusion of trans girls
and women who have benefited from male puberty becomes category defeating.
Conditional inclusion in this context is therefore appropriate. This position will
not satisfy purists on either side of the issue and both have strong arguments in
support of their views. Most immediately, it won’t satisfy those who believe the
category is inevitably defeated by the inclusion of students whose natal sex is male
regardless of how their participation is conditioned. And it won’t satisfy either
medical providers who have built girls sport or invariable inclusion on the basis
of gender identity into their treatment design or trans advocates whose movement
strategy is to elide the differences between sex and identity. Ultimately, however,
the standard that prevails should be one that provides for reasonable
accommodations given institutional goals.
Finally, because the legal landscape has become muddied in this period, to
the point that there are questions about what Title IX does or should require, the
re-commitment to its original design should be codified by statute along with an
allowance for reasonable, non-category defeating accommodations.
230
To the
230. The Obama and Trump Administrations were both put to this question in the context of claims
for transgender inclusion and both have re-affirmed the federal government’s commitment to sex
equality, albeit in different forms. See supra notes 73–75 and accompanying text. But because the
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 131
extent possible the legislation should be based in existing language so as not to
disrupt the well-established body of accompanying law, with definitions and
clarifications as appropriate given the current context. Consistent with this
prescription, we propose the following draft language:
No person shall, on the basis of sex, be excluded from participation in, be denied
the benefits of, be treated differently from another person or otherwise
discriminated against in any interscholastic athletics offered by a recipient, and no
recipient shall provide any such athletics separately on such basis.
However, to secure Title IX’s commitment to sex equality, a recipient may operate
or sponsor separate teams and events based on sex where selection and
advancement are affected by sex-linked competitive advantages or the activity
involved is a contact sport in which physical safety is implicated.
So long as they do not imperil female students’ physical safety or diminish their
competitive opportunities, a recipient that operates or sponsors separate sex teams
and events may include persons of the excluded sex when their gender identity is
concordant. On the same conditions, a recipient that sponsors a team for only one
sex may include persons of the excluded sex. Reasonable accommodations
consistent with these conditions are encouraged.
For purposes of this statute, sex retains its dictionary definition as “either of the
two divisions, designated female and male, by which most organisms are
classified on the basis of their reproductive organs and functions.”
231
It does not
include sex stereotypes or legal or gender identity.
CONCLUSION
Title IX expresses society’s commitment to sex equality in educational
settings. At the time of the statute’s enactment in 1972, this commitment was
revolutionary. Today, in no small part because Americans across the political
spectrum are invested in the goal, Title IX’s value is mostly a given.
232
From the
focus on increasing the numbers of women in STEM to the effort to eradicate the
conditions that enable sexual assault, the idea that women belong as equals on
campus persists. Notably, the commitment to this idea is not merely normative.
As Nicholas Kristof wrote in his year-end column for the New York Times in 2019,
“few forces change the world so much as education and the empowerment of
women.”
233
executive branch has discretion in the interpretation of federal regulations, and because
administrations come and go, they can foster unnecessary confusion and ensure that the matter
remains unsettled.
231. Sex, A
M. HERITAGE DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE (5th ed. 2020).
232. Sandra Guy, Title IX at 45, S
OCY OF WOMEN ENGRS MAG. (Mar. 20, 2017), https://alltogether.
swe.org/2017/03/title-ix-45/ (“Title IX is hugely popular, and it’s a bipartisan issue. We don’t expect
that to change.”).
233. Nicholas Kristof, This Year Has Been The Best Year Ever, N.Y.
TIMES (Dec. 31, 2019), https://ww
w.nytimes.com/2019/12/28/opinion/sunday/2019-best-year-poverty.html. See also Ana Revenga &
Sudhir Shetty, Empowering Women is Smart Economics, 49 IMF F
IN. & DEV. (2012), https://www. imf.org/e
xternal/pubs/ft/fandd/2012/03/revenga.htm.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
132 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
The structure of the Title IX regulatory scheme makes clear that the goal is
sex equality, not sex neutrality. Consistent with American equal protection
jurisprudence and our general political inclinations, the latter is merely the
preferred means to the former end. Like other sex equality measures, Title IX
recognizes that females often remain disadvantaged in relation to males because
of their reproductive biology and because of stereotypes about them based on that
biology. Sex affirmative approaches are appropriate when sex neutrality cannot
effectively address that disadvantage. Thus, such approaches may be used to
overcome entrenched discriminatory patterns that are not explained by inherent
differences; see special provisions for women and girls in fields in which they
remain underrepresented. And they may be used to ensure that such differences
are not unnecessary obstacles to important opportunities; see separate sex sport.
Notwithstanding our general preference for sex neutral measures, the sports
exception to Title IX’s general nondiscrimination rule has long been one of the
statute’s most popular features.
234
This affirmative approach is understood to be
necessary to ensure that the sex-linked differences that emerge from the onset of
male puberty do not stand as obstacles to sex equality in the athletic arena. From
the beginning, it was understood that any different, sex neutral measure would
ensure precisely the opposite—that spaces on selective teams and spots in finals
and on podiums would all go to boys and men. The sports exception makes it
possible for women and girls also to benefit from the multiple positive effects of
these experiences, and for their communities and the broader society to reap the
benefits of their empowerment.
The challenge in the beginning of the Title IX era was to conceive of and
equally to support females as athletes, coaches, and sports administrators. We
continue to fight for equal support as important institutions still stumble—see, for
example, the dearth of female coaches in NCAA programs;
235
Nike’s recently-
revealed failure to keep its brightest female stars under contract when they become
pregnant;
236
and USA Soccer’s refusal to provide equal pay to the members of its
male and female teams.
237
But as Title IX concludes its first semi-centennial, we no
longer struggle as we did in the beginning with the basic concept of females as
athletes. It is no longer commonplace for an athletic department to assume that a
female is on the field to land a husband rather than a medal. Female puberty,
pregnancy, and motherhood remain visible indicia of difference, but because of
234. See supra note 62 and accompanying text (quoting Nancy Hogshead-Makar on this point).
235. Jeré Longman, Number of Women Coaching in College Has Plummeted in Title IX Era, N.
Y. TIMES
(Mar. 30, 2017), https://www.nytimes.com/2017/03/30/sports/ncaabasketball/coaches-women-titleix.ht
ml.
236. Alisia Montaño, Nike Told Me to Dream Crazy, Until I Wanted a Baby, N.
Y. TIMES (May 12, 2019),
https://www.nytimes.com/2019/05/12/opinion/nike-maternity-leave.html. The company was smart
enough to continue to pay Serena Williams through her pregnancy, but other stars—including most
notably Allyson Felix—were not similarly treated. Scott Davis, Serena Williams Supports Nike After Its
Maternity Pay Controversy, Saying the Company Is ‘Learning from Mistakes and Doing Better’, B
US. INSIDER
(May 28, 2019, 12:51 PM), https://www.businessinsider.com/serena-williams-backs-nike-maternity-
pay-controversy-2019-5.
237. Andrew Das, U.S. Women’s Soccer Team Granted Class Status in Equal Pay Lawsuit, N.
Y. TIMES
(Nov. 8, 2019), https://www.nytimes.com/2019/11/08/sports/uswnt-equal-pay-lawsuit.html.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
RE-AFFIRMING THE VALUE OF THE SPORTS EXCEPTION 133
the sports exception, they are no longer disqualifying. Indeed, when the
promotion is done right, these are affirmatively empowering and celebrated.
238
The challenge as we move into Title IX’s second semi-centennial is to
persuade institutions finally to address the remaining disparities in their support
of female athletes and female sport at the same time that we enter a new
revolutionary period in which we are being asked to imagine that “female”
includes individuals of both biological sexes so long as they identify as women
and girls. This ask reflects the intellectual choice to conceive of sex as a social
construct rather than as a fact of biology tied to reproduction, and also the strategic
choice of trans rights advocates to work toward law reform that would disallow
any distinctions on the basis of reproductive sex. A popular manifestation of this
strategy is their insistence that we accept as threshold truth rather than as political
claim the proposition that “Trans women are women, period.”
The problem is that female sport is by design and for good reasons, a
reproductive sex classification. These reasons have nothing to do with transphobia
and everything to do with the performance gap that emerges from the onset of
male puberty. Whether one is trans or not, if one is in sport and cares about sex
equality, this physical phenomenon is undeniably relevant. Changing how we
define “female” so that it includes individuals of both sexes, and then disallowing
any distinctions among them on the basis of sex, is by definition and in effect a
rejection of Title IX’s equality goals. Whatever their earlier allegiances, and
however they would seek to re-tool the relevant vocabulary to obscure this point,
we should be clear that those push for these changes today are committed to sex
neutrality, not to sex equality.
We need to find a path to equality also for trans people. And we need to be
thoughtful about how they are included within an institution whose design is at
odds with who they are. But given the enormous social utility and popularity of
that design, as well as the work that still needs to be done to fulfill its promise, a
path that involves a rejection of its principal terms is a non-starter.
In this paper, we have provided the legal history and the science that make
sense of the sports exception to Title IX’s general nondiscrimination rule. We have
also developed the policy arguments for affirming the commitment to sex equality
in the education-based sports space, and for including trans kids in that space in
ways that support their healthy development without undermining either the
statute’s sex equality goals or its allowance for sex affirmative measures to achieve
them. Finally, we have described and evaluated the options that are and ought to
be on the table as civil rights advocates and policymakers work through this
challenge. We do not expect that we have thought of everything; indeed, because
the science and social norms are evolving as we write, we assume that regular
238. This video from the Olympic Channel, Aiming for the Olympics After Child-Birth ft. Allyson Felix/
Top Performer, Y
OUTUBE (Oct. 21, 2019), https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=TNuL38NRppg is
illustrative. See also, e.g., Annabelle Timsit, Serena Williams’s New Ad Gives Working Moms the Nuanced
Representation They Deserve, Q
UARTZ AT WORK (Aug. 29, 2018), https://qz.com/work/1372139/serena-
williams-thismama-ad-offers-a-powerful-vision-of-working-moms/. For a summary of the
development of the market for female sport, see Ross Andrews, Women’s Sports Popularity is Growing,
According to Nielsen Study, G
LOB. SPORT MATTERS (Nov. 13, 2018), https://globalsportmatters.com/busin
ess/2018/11/13/womens-sports-popularity-is-growing-according-to-nielsen/.
Prof. Coleman- FINAL PAGE PROOF 0305 (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 9:11 AM
134 DUKE JOURNAL OF GENDER LAW & POLICY Volume 27:69 2020
updating will be necessary. But we hope that the structure, background, and
arguments we’ve set out will be useful in the process.